These lectures trace the subtle changes in people's ideas and feelings in connection with the development of natural science. Through this, Steiner shows the significance of scientific research and the mode of thinking that goes with it. As we look at what technology has brought us, we can have a feeling akin to the one of pain over the death of a person. This feeling, Steiner says, will become the most important impetus to seek the spirit.
The nine lectures presented here were given in Dornach from December 24 to 28, 1922 and from January 1 to 6, 1923. In the Collected Edition of Rudolf Steiner's works, the volume containing the German texts is entitled, Der Entstehungsmoment der Naturwissenschaft in der Weltgeschichte und ihre seitherige Entwickelung. (Vol. 326 in the Collected Edition.) These lectures were translated by Maria St. Goar and edited by Norman Macbeth.
∴
Introduction
The nine lectures that follows were delivered by Rudolf Steiner at
the turn of 1922/23 in Dornach, Switzerland. They were directed to an
audience containing some professional scientists and others particularly
interested in science, mangy of whom were members of the
Anthroposophical Society. 1922/23 happens also to have been an
historical moment in the life of the Society and indeed of the lecturer.
No one reading them would suspect that between Lectures 5 and 6 both
parties had been stricken by a crushing blow. On New Year's Eve, 1922,
the building named the Goetheanum, in which the first five lectures had
been given, was totally destroyed by fire and was indeed still burning
on January 1 when Steiner delivered Lecture 6 in his private Studio. The
great wooden structure, a temple rather than a mere headquarters or
meeting-place, had been designed by Steiner himself, its building
supervised by him at all stages, and much of its interior worked with
his own hands; but this is not the place to enlarge on his personal
tragedy or the courage and determination it must have required to
continue with the lecture course on the following day almost as if
nothing had happened. The most that critical appraisal might detect as a
possible consequence of that grievous interruption is perhaps a certain
repetitiveness not apparent elsewhere in either his books or his
lectures; and this the translator has taken the liberty of slightly
reducing.
One more preliminary observation may be desirable. Most members of
the original audience would have been familiar, to a greater or less
degree, with the fundamental teachings and thus with the terminology of
anthroposophy, or spiritual science, as Steiner also named them. Here
and there in the lectures some of that terminology is introduced, for
example "etheric" and "astral," "the Age
of the consciousness soul." Mostly their meaning is briefly
indicated when they first appear; but it remains true that some previous
familiarity with them is of considerable assistance towards a full
understanding, not only of particular passages, but also of the radical
message of the whole.
Their basic argument is that modern science, and the scientism based
on it, so far from being the only possible
"reality-principle" is merely one way of conceiving the
nature of reality; a way moreover that has arisen only recently and
which there is no reason to suppose will last forever. Many today might
admit as much, but in doing so they would be thinking of modern science
mainly as a theory or set of theories capable of proof or disproof by
accepted methods. For Steiner modern science, including its
empirical method, is a stage, and an important stage, in the whole
evolution of human consciousness. And that is something different from,
though it underlies, the history of ideas. Perception itself is
determined by the human psyche, the consciousness which determines
perception precedes the formation of thoughts based on that perception,
and the human psyche is an evolving one. Only hitherto it has not been
conscious of that fact. Certain ideas were formed, and could only be
formed, at certain stages in that evolution. Ideas for instance or
theories about the nature of the world, or the nature of Nature, are
necessarily based on certain "givens" — experiences
taken for granted — which are so immediate that no ideas at all
can be formed about them. Isaac Newton, as Lecture Three points
out, was sufficiently aware of this to declare the "givens"
of his own day as the "postulates" from which he started.
They were time, place, space and motion. And these remain the givens for
our day, even if their slight unsettling by Einstein's relativity should
be the first faint breath of coming winds of change. But they were not
so for other days and other men. They were not so before at most the
fifteenth century. They are given for us, because for us the outer world
of natural objects and events is experienced as completely detached from
the inner world of our own awareness of them, that is to say, from our
humanity. Descartes was the first to formulate this — then
comparatively novel — given, when he divided the world into
extended substance and thinking substance.
Writing in 1818 an essay on Method, Coleridge prophesied:
"... there will soon be seen a general tendency toward, an
earnest seeking after, come ground common to the world and to man,
therein to find the one principle of permanence and identity, the rock
of strength and refuge, to which the soul may cling amid the fleeing
surge-like objects of the sense."
The abiding thrust of these lectures is Steiner's unshakable
conviction that from now on the progress of science will depend on the
overcoming of the received dichotomy between man and nature just as from
the fifteenth or sixteenth century up to now the progress of
science has depended on that dichotomy. Incidental to that
progress would be escape from the crudities of popular scientism, but
the lectures are only marginally concerned with that. Their content is
based on the fact that the understanding, perhaps of any phenomenon but
certainly of any phenomenon so basic as to be "given,"
entails a patient examination of its provenance, that is to say of the
steps by which it came into being. Consequently they are, as the title
suggests, lectures not on science, but on the history of science. In sum
they tell the story of the origin and then of the growth of that gulf
between inner and outer, between subject and object, extending from a
time before Pythagoras down to our own day, as it is manifest in the
writings and biographies of a selection of well-known thinkers.
Particular attention is given to transitional figures, men whose
perceptions were still determined by the past, while their thoughts were
confronted by what was approaching from the future; and perhaps
especially interesting in this regard are the observations of Giordana
Bruno's cosmos in Lecture Four and Galen's theory of
"fermentation" in Lecture Eight.
The story is at the same time one of the steadily increasing
predominance of mathematics in determining scientific method. Perception
of this is not peculiar to Steiner. What distinguishes him from other
historians of science is the psychological detail into which he pursues
the story and, more than that, his account of the origin of
mathematics, The Cartesian coordinates are not as abstract as they seem;
or rather they were not always so. Steiner sees them as an extrapolation
or projection of man's experience of his own body; that is to say, of
his physical body. And here is one of the places where some previous
acquaintance with anthroposophy and its terminology would be helpful,
though it should not indispensable. It is unfortunate that the word
"body" has become, for most people, almost synonymous with
"lump of solid matter;" Particularly unfortunate, where it
is the human body that is at issue, since nine-tenths of that is
composed of fluids, and of fluids that are for the most part in motion.
"Body" in Steiner's terminology, signifies something more
like "systematically organized unit or entity," as distinct
from the matter or substance of which it is composed. Thus, the fact
that the frame of a living human being contains, and not at random,
fluid and airy, as well as solid, substance, entails the existence of
other "bodies" besides the physically organized one. These
are especially relevant when the discourse turns from knowledge of
quantity (measurement and mathematics) to knowledge of quality, an
aspect of nature that is virtually a closed book to the science of
today.
The development of that science of today, a purely quantitative one,
is the main thread on which the lectures are strung, and the reader will
follow it or himself. Not much perhaps would be gained by informing him
in advance that, if he does so, he will be shown for example, how the
projection of mathematics, and particularly the coordinates, outward
from the body and thus from human selfhood, has led to the reification
of space — that long-settled mental habit which advanced psychics
has only recently begun to question. He will also find an answer to a
question which has puzzled many thinkers: why should mathematics,
a seemingly artificial construction of the human brain, have been found
an effective key to unlock so many of the secrets of nature? How is it
that the one has happened to fit so snugly on the other? More generally
he will be led down a sort of ladder of "descent,"
accompanied throughout by mathematics, from man's original psychic
participation in the life of nature to his present detachment from it;
to be shown at the end that an understanding of the way of ascent to
reunion with that life also begins with mathematics. The last is
an aspect of the matter with which Steiner was to deal more specifically
in a subsequent course of lectures translated into English as The
Boundaries of Natural Science.
"Descent" and "ascent" are of course loaded
terms, and their use can be misleading. The same is true of the term
"dehumanization" when in these lectures it is applied to the
history of science. Steiner was no enemy of science, though he
vigorously questioned many of its theories. "Technology" is
not a dirty word in his vocabulary. Pointing to a fact is not
necessarily abuse. Science has become dehumanized in the sense that it
has turned its attention more and more away from human experience and
human values. But in doing so it has furthered, if not partly
engendered, one supreme human value — that detached, individual
self-consciousness that is the pre-condition of freedom. Man has become
separated from the world that gave him birth; but he needed that
separation in order to become truly man. To draw attention to that
separation is, says our lecturer, "a description of the scientific
view, not a criticism." He continues (and I will conclude this
Introduction by quoting the closing words of Lecture Six):
Let us assume that somebody says: "Here I have water. I cannot
use it in this state.I separate the oxygen from the hydrogen,
because I need the hydrogen." He then proceeds to do so.If I
then say what he has done, this is not criticism of his conduct.I
have no business to tell him he is doing something wrong, and should
leave the water alone. Nor is it criticism when I say that since the
Fifteenth Century science has taken the world of living beings and
separated it from the true nature of man, discarding it and retaining
what the age required. It then led this dehumanized science to the
triumphs that have been achieved.
It is not criticism if something like this is said: it is only a
description. The scientist of modern times needed a dehumanized nature,
just as a chemist needs deoxygenized hydrogen and therefore has to split
water into its two components. The point is to understand that we must
not constantly fall into the error of looking to science for an
understanding of man.
My dear friends! You have come together this Christmas, some of you
from distant places, to work in the Goetheanum on some matters in the
field of spiritual science. At the outset of our considerations I would
like to extend to you — especially the friends who have come from
afar — our heartiest Christmas greetings. What I myself, occupied
as I am with the most manifold tasks, will be able to offer you at this
particular time can only be indications in one or another direction.
Such indications as will be offered in my lectures, and in those of
others, will, we hope, result in a harmony of feeling and thinking among
those gathered together here in the Goetheanum. It is also my hope that
those friends who are associated with the Goetheanum and more or less
permanently residing here will warmly welcome those who have come from
elsewhere. Through our working, thinking and feeling together, there
will develop what must be the very soul of all endeavors at the
Goetheanum; namely, our perceiving and working out of the spiritual life
and essence of the world.
If this ideal increasingly becomes a reality, if the efforts of
individuals interested in the anthroposophical world conception flow
together in true social cooperation, in mutual give and take, then there
will emerge what is intended to emerge at the Goetheanum. In this
spirit, I extend the heartiest welcome to those friends who have come
here from afar as well as to those residing more permanently in Dornach.
The indication that I shall try to give in this lecture course will
not at first sight appear to be related to the thought and feeling of
Christmas, yet inwardly, I believe, they are so related. In all that is
to be achieved at the Goetheanum, we are striving toward the birth of
something new, toward knowledge of the spirit, toward a feeling
consecrated to the spirit, toward a will sustained by the spirit. This
is in a sense the birth of a super-sensible spiritual element and, in a
very real way, symbolizes the Christmas thought, the birth of that
spiritual Being who produced a renewal of all human evolution upon
earth. Therefore, our present studies are, after all, imbued with the
character of a Christmas study.
Our aim in these lectures is to establish the moment in history when
the scientific mode of thinking entered mankind's development. This does
not conflict with what I have just said. If you remember what I
described many years ago in my book Mysticism at the Dawn of the
Modern Age, [1] you will perceive my
conviction that beneath the external trappings of scientific conceptions
one can see the first beginnings of a new spirituality. My opinion,
based on objective study, is that the scientific path taken by modern
humanity was, if rightly understood, not erroneous but entirely proper.
Moreover, if regarded in the right way, it bears within itself the seed
of a new perception and a new spiritual activity of will. It is from
this point of view that I would like to give these lectures. They will
not aim at any kind of opposition to science. The aim and intent is
instead to discover the seeds of spiritual life in the highly productive
modern methods of scientific research. On many occasions I have pointed
this out in various way. In lectures given at various times on various
areas of natural scientific thinking, [2] I have given details of the path that I want to
characterize in broader outline during the present lectures.
If we want to acquaint ourselves with the real meaning of scientific
research in recent times and the mode of thinking that can and does
underlie it, we must go back several centuries into the past. The
essence of scientific thinking is easily misunderstood, if we look only
at the immediate present. The actual nature of scientific research
cannot be understood unless its development is traced through several
centuries. We must go back to a point in time that I have often
described as very significant in modern evolution; namely, the
fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. At that time, an altogether
different form of thinking, which was still active through the Middle
Ages, was supplanted by the dawn of the present-day mode of thought. As
we look back into this dawn of the modern age, in which many memories of
the past were still alive, we encounter a man in whom we can see, as it
were, the whole transition from an earlier to a later form of thinking.
He is Cardinal Nicholas Cusanus, [3] (Nicholas of Cusa) a renowned churchman and one of
the greatest thinkers of all time. He was born in 1401, the son of a
boatman and vinegrower in the Rhine country of Western Germany, and died
in 1464, a persecuted ecclesiastic. [4] Though he may have understood himself quite well,
Cusanus was a person who is in some respects extremely difficult for a
modern student to comprehend.
Cusanus received his early education in the community that has been
called "The Brethren of the Common Life." [5] There he
absorbed his earliest impressions, which were of a peculiar kind. It is
clear that Nicholas already possessed a certain amount of ambition as a
boy, but this was tempered by an extraordinary gift for comprehending
the needs of the social life of his time. In the community of the
Brethren of the Common Life, persons were gathered together who were
dissatisfied with the church institutions and with the monastic and
religious orders that, though within the church, were to some degree in
opposition to it.
In a manner of speaking, the Brethren of the Common Life were
mystical revolutionaries. They wanted to attain what they regarded as
their ideal purely by intensification of a life spent in peace and human
brotherhood. They rejected any rulership based on power, such as was
found in a most objectionable form in the official church at that time.
They did not want to become estranged from the world as were members of
monastic orders. They stressed physical cleanliness; they insisted that
each one should faithfully and diligently perform his duty in external
life and in his profession. They did not want to withdraw from the
world. In a life devoted to genuine work they only wanted to withdraw
from time to time into the depths of their souls. Alongside the external
reality of life, which they acknowledged fully in a practical sense,
they wanted to discover the depths and inwardness of religious and
spiritual feeling. Theirs was a community that above all else cultivated
human qualities in an atmosphere where a certain intimacy with God and
contemplation of the spirit might abide. It was in this community
— at Deventer in Holland — that Cusanus was educated. The
majority of the members were people who, in rather narrow circles,
fulfilled their duties, and sought in their quiet chambers for God and
the spiritual world.
Cusanus, on the other hand, was by nature disposed to be active in
outer life and, through the strength of will springing from his
knowledge, to involve himself in organizing social life. Thus Cusanus
soon felt impelled to leave the intimacy of life in the brotherhood and
enter the outer world. At first, he accomplished this by studying
jurisprudence. It must be borne in mind, however, that at that time
— the early Fifteenth Century — the various sciences were
less specialized and had many more points of contact than was the case
later on.
So for a while Cusanus practiced law. His was an era, however, in
which chaotic factors extended into all spheres of social life. He
therefore soon wearied of his law practice and had himself ordained a
priest of the Roman Catholic Church. He always put his whole heart into
whatever he did, and so he now became a true priest of the Papal church.
He worked in this capacity in the various clerical posts assigned to
him, and he was particularly active at the Council of Basle
(1431–1449). [6] There he
headed a minority whose ultimate aim it was to uphold the absolute power
of the Holy See. [7] The majority, consisting for the most part of
bishops and cardinals from the West, were striving after a more
democratic form, so to speak, of church administration. The pope, they
thought, should be subordinated to the councils. This led to a schism in
the Council. Those who followed Cusanus moved the seat of the Council to
the South; the others remained in Basle and set up an anti-pope. [8]
Cusanus remained firm in his defense of an absolute papacy. With a
little insight it is easy to imagine the feelings that impelled Cusanus
to take this stand. He must have felt that whatever emerged from a
majority could at best lead only to a somewhat sublimated form of the
same chaos already existing in his day. What he wanted was a firm hand
that would bring about law and order, though he did want firmness
permeated with insight. When he was sent to Middle Europe later on, he
made good this desire by upholding consolidation of the Papal church.
[9]
He was therefore, as a matter of
course, destined to become a cardinal of the Papal church of that
time.
As I said earlier, Nicholas probably understood himself quite well,
but a latter-day observer finds him hard to understand. This becomes
particularly evident when we see this defender of absolute papal power
traveling from place to place and — if the words he then spoke are
taken at face value — fanatically upholding the papistical
Christianity of the West against the impending danger of a Turkish
invasion. [10]
On the one hand, Cusanus (who in all likelihood had already been made a
cardinal by that time) spoke in flaming words against the infidels. In
vehement terms he summoned Europe to unite in resistance to the Turkish
threat from Asia. On the other hand, if we study a book that Cusanus
probably composed [11] in the very midst of
his inflammatory campaigns against the Turks, we find something strange.
In the first place, Cusanus preaches in the most rousing manner against
the imminent danger posed by the Turks, inciting all good men to defend
themselves against this peril and thus save European civilization. But
then Cusanus sits down at his desk and writes a treatise on how
Christians and Jews, pagans and Moslems — provided they are
rightly understood — can be brought to peaceful cooperation, to
the worship and recognition of the one universal God; how in Christians,
Jews, Moslems and heathens there dwells a common element that need only
be discovered to create peace among mankind. Thus the most conciliatory
sentiments in regard to religions and denominations flow from this man's
quiet private chamber, while he publicly calls for war in the most
fanatical words.
This is what makes it hard to understand a man like Nicholas
Cusanus. Only real insight that age can make him comprehensible but he
must be viewed in the context of the inner spiritual development of his
time. No criticism is intended. We only want to see the external side of
this man, with the furious activity that I have described, and then to
see what was living in his soul. We simply want to place the two aspects
side by side.
We can best observe what took place in Cusanus's mind if we study
the mood he was in while returning from a mission to Constantinople
[12] on the behalf of the Holy See. His task was to work
for the reconciliation of the Western and Eastern churches. On his
return voyage, when he was on the ship and looking at the stars, there
arose in him the fundamental thought, the basic feeling, incorporated in
the book that he published in 1440 under the title De Docta
Ignorantia (On Learned Ignorance). [13]
What is the mood of this book? Cardinal Cusanus had, of course, long
since absorbed all the spiritual knowledge current in the Middle Ages.
He was well versed also in what the medieval schools of Neo-Platonism
and Neo-Aristotelianism had attained. He was also quite familiar with
the way Thomas Aquinas had spoken of the spiritual worlds as though it
were the most normal thing for human concepts to rise from sense
perception to spirit perception. In addition to his mastery of medieval
theology, he had a thorough knowledge of the mathematical conceptions
accessible to men of that time. He was an exceptionally good
mathematician. His soul, therefore, was filled on the one side with the
desire to rise through theological concepts to the world of spirit that
reveals itself to man as the divine and, on the other side, with all the
inner discipline, rigor and confidence that come to a man who immerses
himself in mathematics. Thus he was both a fervent and an accurate
thinker.
When he was crossing the sea from Constantinople to the West and
looking up at the starlit sky, his twofold soul mood characterized above
revolved itself in the following feeling. Thenceforth, Cusanus conceived
the deity as something lying outside human knowledge. He told himself:
"We can live here on earth with our knowledge, with our concepts
and thoughts. By means of these we can take hold of what surrounds us in
the kingdom of nature. But these concepts grow ever more lame when we
direct our gaze upward to what reveals itself as the divine."
In Scholasticism, arising from quite another viewpoint, a gap had
opened up between knowledge and revelation.
[14] This gap now became the deepest problem of Cusanus's
soul, the most intimate concern of the heart. Repeatedly he sent through
this course of reasoning, repeatedly he saw how thinking extends itself
over everything surrounding man in nature; how it then tries to raise
itself above this realm to the divinity of thoughts; and how, there, it
becomes ever more tenuous until it finally completely dissipates into
nothingness as it realizes that the divine lies beyond that void into
which thinking has dissipated. Only if a man has developed (apart form
this life in thought) sufficient fervent love to be capable of
continuing further on this path that his though has traversed, only if
love gains the lead over thought, then this love can attain the realm
into which knowledge gained only by thinking cannot reach.
It therefore became a matter of deep concern for Cusanus to
designate the actual divine realm as the dimension before which human
thought grows lame and human knowledge is dispersed into nothingness.
This was his docta ignorantia, his learned ignorance. Nicholas
Cusanus felt that when erudition, knowledge, assumes in the noblest
sense a state of renouncing itself at the instant when it thinks to
attain the spirit, then it achieves its highest form, it becomes
docta ignorantia. It was in this mood that Cusanus published his
De Docta Ignorantia in 1440.
Let us leave Cusanus for the moment, and look into the lonely cell
of a medieval mystic who preceded Cusanus. To the extent that this man
has significance for spiritual science, I described him in my book on
mysticism. He is Meister Eckhart, [15] a man who was declared a heretic by the
official church. There are many ways to study the writings of Meister
Eckhart and one can delight in the fervor of his mysticism. It is
perhaps most profoundly touching if, through repeated study, the reader
comes upon a fundamental mood of Eckhart's soul.
I would like to describe it as follows. Though living earlier than
Cusanus, Meister Eckhart too was imbued through and through with what
medieval Christian theology sought as an ascent to the divine, to the
spiritual world. When we study Meister Eckhart's writings, we can
recognize Thomistic shades of thought in many of his lines. But each
time Meister Eckhart's soul tries to rise from theological thinking to
the actual spiritual world (with which it feels united,) it ends
By saying to itself that with all this thinking and theology it
cannot penetrate to its innermost essence, to the divine inner spark. It
tells itself: This thinking, this theology, these ideas, give me
fragments of something here, there, everywhere. But none of these are
anything like the spiritual divine spark in my own inner being.
Therefore, I am excluded from all thoughts, feelings, and memories that
fill my soul, from all knowledge of the world that I can absorb up to
the highest level. I am excluded from it all, even though I am seeking
the deepest nature of my own being. I am in nothingness when I seek this
essence of myself. I have searched and searched. I traveled many paths,
and they brought me many ideas and feelings, and on these paths I found
much. I searched for my "I," but before ever I found it, I
fell into "nothingness" in this search for the
"I," although all the kingdoms of nature urged me to the
search.
So, in his search for the self, Meister Eckhart felt that he had
fallen into nothingness. This feeling evoked in this medieval mystic
words that profoundly touch the heart and soul. They can be paraphrased
thus: "I submerge myself in God's nothingness, and am eternally,
through nothingness, through nothing, an I; through nothing, I become an
I. In all eternity, I must etch the I from the 'nothingness'
of God." [16] These are
powerful words. Why did this urge for "nothing," for finding
that I in nothingness, resound in the innermost chamber of this mystic's
heart, when he wanted to pass from seeking the world to seeking the I?
Why? If we go back into earlier times, we find that in former ages it
was possible, when the soul turned its gaze inward into itself, to
behold the spirit shining forth within. This was still a heritage of
primeval pneumatology, of which we shall speak later on. When Thomas
Aquinas, for example, peered into the soul, he found within the soul a
weaving, living spiritual element. Thomas Aquinas [17] and his
predecessors sought the essential ego not in the soul itself but in the
spiritual dwelling in the soul. They looked through the soul into the
spirit, and in the spirit they found their God-given I. And they said,
or could have said: I penetrate into my inmost soul, gaze into the
spirit, and in the spirit I find the I. — In the meantime,
however, in humanity's forward development toward the realm of freedom,
men had lost the ability to find the spirit when they looked inward into
themselves.
An earlier figure such as John Scotus Erigena (810–880) would
not have spoken as did Meister Eckhart. He would have said: I gaze into
my being. When I have traversed all the paths that led me through the
kingdoms of the outer world, then I discover the spirit in my inmost
soul. Thereby, I find the "I" weaving and living in the
soul. I sink myself as spirit into the Divine and discover
"I."
It was, alas, human destiny that the path that was still accessible
to mankind in earlier centuries was no longer open in Meister Eckhart's
time. Exploring along the same avenues as John Scotus Erigena or even
Thomas Aquinas, Meister Eckhart could not sink himself into
God-the-Spirit, but only into the "nothingness" of the
Divine, and from this "nothing" he had to take hold of the
I. This shows that mankind could no longer see the spirit in inner
vision. Meister Eckhart brought the I out of the naught through the deep
fervor of his heart. His successor, Nicholas Cusanus, [18] admits with complete candor: All thoughts and
ideas that lead us in our exploration of the world become lame, become
as nothing, when we would venture into the realm of spirit. The soul has
lost the power to find the spirit realm in its inner being. So Cusanus
says to himself: When I experience everything that theology can give me,
I am led into this naught of human thinking. I must unite myself with
what dwells in this nothingness in order to at least gain in the
docta ignorantia the experience of the spirit. — Then,
however, such knowledge, such perception, cannot be expressed in words.
Man is rendered dumb when he has reached the point at which he can
experience the spirit only through the docta ignorantia.
Thus Cusanus is the man who in his own personal development
experiences the end of medieval theology and is driven to the docta
ignorantia. He is, however, at the same time a skillful
mathematician. He has the disciplined thinking that derives from the
pursuit of mathematics. But he shies away, as it were, from applying his
mathematical skills to the docta ignorantia. He approaches the
docta ignorantia with all kinds of mathematical symbols and
formulas, but he does this timidly, diffidently. He is always conscious
of the fact that these are symbols derived from mathematics. He says to
himself: Mathematics is the last remnant left to me from ancient
knowledge. I cannot doubt its reliability as I can doubt that of
theology, because I actually experience its reliability when I apprehend
mathematics with my mind. — At the same time, his disappointment
with theology is so great he dares not apply his mathematical skills in
the field of the docta ignorantia except in the form of
symbols.
This is the end of one epoch in human thinking. In his inner mood of
soul, Cusanus was almost as much of a mathematician as was Descartes
later on, but he dared not try to grasp with mathematics what appeared
to him in the manner he described in his Docta Ignorantia He felt
as though the spirit realm had withdrawn from mankind, had vanished
increasingly into the distance, and was unattainable with human
knowledge. Man must become ignorant in the innermost sense in order to
unite himself in love with this realm of the spirit.
This mood pervades Cusanus's Docta Ignorantia published in
1440. In the development of Western civilization, men had once believed
that they confronted the spirit-realm in close perspective. But then,
this spirit realm became more and more remote from those men who
observed it, and finally it vanished. The book of 1440 was a frank
admission that the ordinary human comprehension of that time could no
longer reach the remote perspectives into which the spirit realm has
withdrawn. Mathematics, the most reliable of the sciences, dared to
approach only with symbolic formulas what was no longer beheld by the
soul. It was as though this spirit realm, receding further and further
in perspective, had disappeared from European civilization. But from the
opposite direction, another realm was coming increasingly into view.
This was the realm of the sense world, which European civilization was
beginning to observe and like. In 1440, Nicholas Cusanus applied
mathematical thinking and mathematical knowledge to the vanishing spirit
realm only by a timid use of symbols; but now Nicholas Copernicus boldly
and firmly applied them to the outer sense world. In 1440 the Docta
Ignorantia appeared with the admission that even with mathematics
one can no longer behold the spirit realm. We must conceive the spirit
realm as so far removed from human perception that even mathematics can
approach it only with halting symbols; this is what Nicholas Cusanus
said in 1440. "Conceive of mathematics as so powerful and reliable
that it can force the sense world into mathematical formulas that are
scientifically understandable." This is what Nicholas Copernicus
said to European civilization in 1543. In 1543 Copernicus published his
De Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium (On the Revolutions of the
Celestial Bodies,) where the universe was depicted so boldly and
rudely that it had to surrender itself to mathematical treatment.
One century lies between the two. During this century Western
science was born. Earlier, it had been in an embryonic state. Whoever
wants to understand what led to the birth of Western science, must
understand this century that lies between the Docta Ignorantia
and the De Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium. Even today, if we
are to understand the true meaning of science, we must study the
fructifications that occurred at that time in human soul life and the
renunciations it had to experience. We must go back this far in time. If
we want to have the right scientific attitude, we must begin there, and
we must also briefly consider the embryonic state preceding Nicholas
Cusanus. Only then can we really comprehend what science can accomplish
for mankind and see how new spiritual life can blossom forth from
it.
∴
Lecture II
25 December 1922, Dornach
The view of history forming the basis of these lectures may be called
symptomatological What takes place in the depths of human evolution
sends out waves, and these waves are the symptoms that we will try to
describe and interpret. In any serious study of history, this must be
the case. The processes and events occurring at any given time in the
depths of evolution are so manifold and so significant that we can never
do more than hint at what is going on the depths. This we do by
describing the waves that are flung up. They are symptoms of what is
actually taking place.
I mention this because, in order to characterize the birth of the
scientific form of thinking and research I described two men, Meister
Eckhart and Nicholas Cusanus, in my last lecture. What can be
historically observed in the soul and appearance of such men I consider
to be symptoms of what goes on in the depths of general human
development; this is why I give such descriptions. There are in any
given case only a couple of images cast up to the surface that we can
intercept by looking into one or another soul. Yet, by doing this, we
can describe the basic nature of successive time periods.
When I described Cusanus yesterday, my intention was to suggest how
all that happened in the early fifteenth century in mankind's spiritual
development, which was pressing forward to the scientific method of
perception, is symptomatically revealed in his soul. Neither the
knowledge that the mind can gather through the study of theology nor the
precise perceptions of mathematics can lead any longer to a grasp of the
spiritual world. The wealth of human knowledge, its concepts and ideas,
come to a halt before that realm. The fact that one can do no more than
write a "docta ignorantia" in the face of the spiritual
world comes to expression in Cusanus in a remarkable way. He could go no
further with the form of knowledge that, up to his time, was prevalent
in human development.
As I pointed out, this soul mood was already present in Meister
Eckhart. He was well versed in medieval theological knowledge. With it,
he attempted to look into this own soul and to find therein the way to
the divine spiritual foundations. Meister Eckhart arrived at a soul mood
that I illustrated with one his sentences. He said — and he made
many similar statements — "I sink myself into the naught of
the divine, and out of nothing become an I in eternity." He felt
himself arriving at nothingness with traditional knowledge. Out of this
nothingness, after the ancient wisdom's loss of all persuasive power he
had to produce out of his own soul the assurance of his own I, and he
did it by this statement.
Looking into this matter more closely, we see how a man like Meister
Eckhart points to an older knowledge that has come down to him through
the course of evolution. It is knowledge that still gave man something
of which he could say: This lives in me, it is something divine in me,
it is something. But now, in Meister Eckhart's own time, the most
profound thinkers had been reduced to the admission: When I seek this
something here or there, all knowledge of this something does not
suffice to bring me certainty of my own being. I must proceed from the
Something to the Nothing and then, in an act of creation, kindle to life
the consciousness of self out of naught.
Now, I want to place another man over against these two. This other
man lived 2,000 years earlier and for his time he was as characteristic
as Cusanus (who followed in Meister Eckhart's footsteps) was for the
fifteenth century. This backward glance into ancient times is necessary
so that we can better understand the quest for knowledge that surfaced
in the Fifteenth Century from the depths of the human soul. The man whom
I want to speak about today is not mentioned in any history book or
historical document, for these do not go back as far as the Eighth
Century B.C. Yet, we can only gain information concerning the origin of
science if, through spiritual science, through purely spiritual
observation, we go farther back than external historical documents can
take us. The man I have in mind lived about 2,000 years prior to the
present period (the starting point of which I have assigned to the first
half of the fifteenth century.) This man of pre-Christian times was
accepted into a so-called mystery school of Southeastern Europe. There
he heard everything that the teachers of the mysteries could communicate
to their pupils concerning spiritual wisdom, truths concerning the
spiritual beings that lived and still live in the cosmos. But the wisdom
that this man received from his teachers was already more or less
traditional. It was a recollection of far older visions, a
recapitulation of what wise men of a much more ancient age had beheld
when they directed their clairvoyant sight into the cosmic spaces whence
the motions and constellations of the stars had spoken to them. To the
sages of old, the universe was not the machine, the mechanical
contraption that it is for men of today when they look out into space to
the wise men of ancient times. The cosmic spaces were like living
beings, permeating everything with spirit and speaking to them in cosmic
language. They experienced themselves within the spirit of world being.
They felt how this, in which they lived and moved, spoke to them, how
they could direct their questions concerning the riddles of the universe
to the universe itself and how, out of the widths of space, the cosmic
phenomena replied to them. This is how they experienced what we, in a
weak and abstract way, call "spirit" in our language. Spirit
was experienced as the element that is everywhere and can be perceived
from anywhere. Men perceived things that even the Greeks no longer
beheld with the eye of the soul, things that had faded into a
nothingness for the Greeks.
This nothingness of the Greeks, which had been filled with living
content for the earliest wise men of the Post-Atlantean age, [19]
was named by means of words
customary for that time. Translated into our language, though weakened
and abstract, those words would signify "spirit." What later
became the unknown, the hidden god, was called spirit in those ages when
he was known. This is the first thing to know about those ancient
times.
The second thing to know is that when a man looked with his soul and
spirit vision into himself, he beheld his soul. He experienced it as
originating from the spirit that later on became the unknown god. The
experience of the ancient sage was such that he designated the human
soul with a term that would translate in our language into "spirit
messenger" or simply "messenger."
If we put into a diagram what was actually seen in those earliest
times, we can say: The spirit was considered the world-embracing
element, apart from which there was nothing and by which everything was
permeated. This spirit, which was directly perceptible in its archetypal
form, was sought and found in the human soul, inasmuch as the latter
recognized itself as the messenger of this spirit. Thus the soul was
referred to as the "messenger."
If we put into a diagram what was actually seen in those earliest
times, we can say: The spirit was considered the world-embracing
element, apart from which there was nothing and by which everything was
permeated. This spirit, which was directly perceptible in its archetypal
form, was sought and found in the human soul, inasmuch as the latter
recognized itself as the messenger of this spirit. Thus the soul was
referred to as the "messenger."
A third aspect was external nature with all that today is called the
world of physical matter, of bodies. I said above that apart from spirit
there was nothing, because spirit was perceived by direct vision
everywhere in its archetypal form. It was seen in the soul, which
realized the spirit's message in its own life. But the spirit was
likewise recognized in what we call nature today, the world of corporeal
things. Even his bodily world was looked upon as an image of the
spirit.
In those ancient times, people did not have the conceptions that we
have today of the physical world. Wherever they looked, at whatever
thing or form of nature, they beheld an image of the spirit, because
they were still capable of seeing the spirit, a fragment of nature.
Inasmuch as all other phenomena of nature were images of the spirit, the
body of man too was an image of the spirit. So when this ancient man
looked at himself, he recognized himself as a threefold being. In the
first place, the spirit lived in him as in one of its many mansions. Man
knew himself as spirit. Secondly, man experienced himself within the
world as a messenger of this spirit, hence as a soul being. Thirdly, man
experienced his corporeality; and by means of this body he felt himself
to be an image of the spirit. [20] Hence, when man looked upon his own being,
he perceived himself as a threefold entity of spirit, soul, and body: as
spirit in his archetypal form; as soul, the messenger of god; as body,
the image of the spirit.
This ancient wisdom contained no contradiction between body and soul
or between nature and spirit; because one knew: Spirit is in man in its
archetypal form; the soul is none other than the message transmitted by
spirit; the body is the image of spirit. Likewise, no contract was felt
between man and surrounding nature because one bore an image of spirit
in one's own body, and the same was true of every body in external
nature. Hence, an inner kinship was experienced between one's own body
and those in outer nature, and nature was not felt to be different from
oneself. Man felt himself at one with the whole world. He could feel
this because he could behold the archetype of spirit and because the
cosmic expanses spoke to him. In consequence of the universe speaking to
man, science simply could not exist. Just as we today cannot build a
science of external nature out of what lives in our memory, ancient man
could not develop one because, whether he looked into himself or outward
at nature, he beheld the same image of spirit. No contrast existed
between man himself and nature, and there was none between soul and
body. The correspondence of soul and body was such that, in a manner of
speaking, the body was only the vessel, the artistic reproduction, of
the spiritual archetype, while the soul was the mediating messenger
between the two. Everything as in a state of intimate union. There could
be no question of comprehending anything. We grasp and comprehend what
is outside our own life. Anything that we carry within ourselves is
directly experienced and need not be first comprehended.
Prior to Roman and Greek times, this wisdom born of direct
perception still lived in the mysteries. The man I referred to above
heard about his wisdom, but he realized that the teachers in his mystery
school were speaking to him only out of a tradition preserved from
earlier ages. He no longer heard anything original, anything gained by
listening to the secrets of the cosmos. This man undertook long journeys
and visited other mystery centers, but it was the same wherever he went.
Already in the Eight Century B.C., only traditions of the ancient wisdom
were preserved everywhere. The pupils learned them from the teachers,
but the teachers could no longer see them, at least not in the vividness
of ancient times.
But this man whom I have in mind had an unappeasable urge for
certainty and knowledge. From the communications passed on to him, he
gathered that once upon a time men had indeed been able to hear the
harmony of the spheres from which resounded the Logos that was identical
with the spiritual archetype of all things. Now, however, it was all
tradition. Just as 2,000 years later Meister Eckhart, working out the
traditions of his age, withdrew into his quiet monastic cell in search
of the inner power source of soul and self, and at length came to say,
"I sink myself into the nothingness of God, and experience in
eternity, in naught, the 'I'," — just so, the
lonely disciple of the late mysteries said to himself: "I listen
to the silent universe and fetch [21] the Logos-bearing soul out of the silence. I
love the Logos because the Logos brings tidings of an unknown
god."
This was an ancient parallel to the admission of Meister Eckhart.
Just as the latter immersed himself into the naught of the divine that
Medieval theology had proclaimed to him and, out of this void, brought
out the "I," so that ancient sage listened to a dumb and
silent world; for he could no longer hear what traditional wisdom taught
him. The spirit-saturated soul had one drawn the ancient wisdom from the
universe. This had not turned silent, but still he had a Logos-bearing
soul. And he loved the Logos even though it was no longer the godhead of
former ages, but only an image of the divine. In other words, already
then, the spirit had vanished from the soul's sight. Just as Meister
Eckhart later had to seek the "I" in nothingness, so at that
time the soul had to be sought in the dispirited world.
Indeed, in former times the souls had the inner firmness needed to
say to themselves: In the inward perception of the spirit indwelling me,
I myself am something divine. But now, for direct perception, the spirit
no longer inhabited the soul. No longer did the soul experience itself
as the spirit's messenger, for one must know something in order to be
its messenger. Now, the soul only felt itself as the bearer of the
Logos, the spirit image; though this spirit image was vivid in the soul.
It expressed itself in the love for this god who thus still lived in his
image in the soul. But the soul no longer felt like the messenger, only
the carrier, of an image of the divine spirit. One can say that a
different form of knowledge arose when man looked into his inner being.
The soul declined from messenger to bearer.
Soul: Bearer
Body: Force
Since the living spirit had been lost to human perception, the body
no longer appeared as the image of spirit. To recognize it as such an
image, one would have had to perceive the archetype. Therefore, for this
later age, the body changed into something that I would like to call
"force." The concept of force emerged. The body was pictured
as a complex of forces, no longer as a reproduction, an image, that bore
within itself the essence of what it reproduced. The human body became a
force which no longer bore the substance of the source from which it
originated.
Not only the human body, but in all of nature, too, forces had to be
pictured everywhere. Whereas formerly, nature in all its aspects had
been an image of spirit, now it had become forces flowing out of the
spirit. This, however, implied that nature began to be something more or
less foreign to man. One could say that the soul had lost something
since it no longer contained direct spirit awareness. Speaking crudely,
I would have to say that the soul had inwardly become more tenuous,
while the body, the external corporeal world, had gained in robustness.
Earlier, as an image, it still possessed some resemblance to the spirit.
Now it became permeated by the element of force. The complex of forces
is more robust than the image in which the spiritual element is still
recognizable. Hence, again speaking crudely, the corporeal world became
denser while the soul became more tenuous. This is what arose in the
consciousness of the men among whom lived the ancient wise man mentioned
above, who listened to the silent universe and from its silence, derived
the awareness that at least his soul was a Logos-bearer.
Now, a contrast that had not existed before arose between the soul,
grown more tenuous, and the increased density of the corporeal world.
Earlier, the unity of spirit had been perceived in all things. Now,
there arose the contrast between body and soul, man and nature. Now
appeared a chasm between body and soul that had not been present at all
prior to the time of this old sage. Man now felt himself divided as well
from nature, something that also had not been the case in the ancient
times. This contrast is the central trait of all thinking in the span of
time between the old sage I have mentioned and Nicholas Cusanus.
Men now struggle to comprehend the connection between, on one hand,
the soul, that lacks spirit reality, and on the other hand, the body
that has become dense, has turned into force, into a complex of
forces.
And men struggle to feel and experience the relationship between man
and nature. But everywhere, nature is force. In that time, no conception
at all existed as yet of what we call today "the laws of
nature." People did not think in terms of natural laws; everywhere
and in everything they felt the forces of nature. When a man looked into
his own being, he did not experience a soul that — as was the case
later one — bore within itself a dim will, an almost equally dim
feeling, and an abstract thinking. Instead, he experienced the soul as
the bearer of the living Logos, something that was not abstract and
dead, but a divine living image of God.
We must be able to picture this contrast, which remained acute until
the eleventh or Twelfth century. It was quite different from the
contrasts that we feel today. If we cannot vividly grasp this contrast,
which was experienced by everyone in that earlier epoch, we make the
same mistake as all those historians of philosophy who regard the old
Greek thinker Democritus [22] of the fifth century B.C. as an atomist in
the modern sense, because he spoke of "atoms." The words
suggest a resemblance, but no real resemblance exists. There is great
difference between modern-day atomists and Democritus. His utterances
were based on the awareness of the contrast described above between man
and nature, soul and body. His atoms were complexes of force and as such
were contrasted with space, something a modern atomist cannot do in that
manner. How could the modern atomist say what Democritus said:
"Existence is not more than nothingness, fullness is not more than
emptiness?" It implies that Democritus assumed empty space to
possess an affinity with atom-filled space. This has meaning only within
a consciousness that as yet has no idea of the modern concept of body.
Therefore, it cannot speak of the atoms of a body, but only of centers
of force, which, in that case, have an inner relationship to what
surrounds man externally. Today's atomist cannot equate emptiness with
fullness. If Democritus had viewed emptiness the way we do today, he
could not have equated it with the state of being. He could do so
because in this emptiness he sought the soul that was the bearer of the
Logos. And though he conceived his Logos in a form of necessity, it was
the Greek form of necessity, not our modern physical necessity. If we
are to comprehend what goes on today, we must be able to look in the
right way into the nuances of ideas and feelings of former times.
There came the time, described in the last lecture, of Meister
Eckhart and Nicholas Cusanus, when even awareness of the Logos
indwelling the soul was lost. The ancient sage, in listening to the
universe, only had to mourn the silence, but Meister Eckhart and Cusanus
found the naught and had to seek the I out of nothingness. Only now, at
this point, does the modern era of thinking begin. The soul now no
longer contains the living Logos. Instead, when it looks into itself, it
finds ideas and concepts, which finally lead to abstractions. The soul
has become even more tenuous. A third phase begins. Once upon a time, in
the first phase, the soul experienced the spirit's archetype within
itself. It saw itself as the messenger of spirit. In the second phase,
the soul inwardly experienced the living image of God in the Logos, it
became the bearer of the Logos.
Now, in the third phase, the soul becomes, as it were, a vessel for
ideas and concepts. These may have the certainty of mathematics, but
they are only ideas and concepts. The soul experiences itself at its
most tenuous, if I may put it so. Again the corporeal world increases in
robustness. This is the third way in which man experiences himself. He
cannot as yet give up his soul element completely, but he experiences it
as the vessel for the realm of ideas. He experiences his body, on the
other hand, not only as a force but as a spatial body.
Soul: Realm of Ideas
Body: Spatial Corporeality
The body has become still more robust. Man now denies the spirit
altogether. Here we come to the "body" that Hobbes, Bacon,
[23]
and Locke
spoke of. Here, we meet "body" at its densest. The soul no
longer feels a kinship to it, only an abstract connection that gets
worse in the course of time.
In place of the earlier concrete contrast of soul and body, man and
nature, another contrast arises that leads further and further into
abstraction. The soul that formerly appeared to itself as something
concrete — because it experienced in itself the Logos-image of the
divine — gradually transforms itself to a mere vessel of ideas.
Whereas before, in the ancient spiritual age, it had felt akin to
everything, it now sees itself as subject and regards everything else as
object, feeling no further kinship with anything.
The earlier contrast of soul and body, man and nature, increasingly
became the merely theoretical epistemological contrast between the
subject that is within a person and the object without. Nature changed
into the object of knowledge. It is not surprising that out of its own
needs knowledge henceforth strove for the "purely
objective."
But what is this purely objective? It is no longer what nature was
to the Greeks. The objective is external corporeality in which no spirit
is any longer perceived. It is nature devoid of spirit, to be
comprehended from without by the subject.
Precisely because man had lost the connection with nature, he now
sought a science of nature from outside. Here, we have once again
reached the point where I concluded yesterday. Cusanus looked upon what
should have been the divine world to him and declared that man with his
knowledge must stop short before it and, if he must write about the
divine world, he must write a docta ignorantia. And only faintly,
in symbols taken from mathematics, did Cusanus want to retain something
of what appeared thus to him as the spiritual realms.
About a hundred years after the Docta Ignorantia appeared in
1440, the De Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium appeared in 1543.
one century later, Copernicus, with his mathematical mind, took hold of
the other side, the external side of what Cusanus could not fully grasp,
not even symbolically, with mathematics. Today, we see how in fact the
application of this mathematical mind to nature becomes possible the
moment that nature vanishes from man's immediate experience. This can be
traced even in the history of language since "Nature" refers
to something that is related to "being born," whereas what
we consider as nature today is only the corporeal world in which
everything is dead. I mean that it is dead for us since, of course,
nature contains life and spirit. But it has become lifeless for us and
the most certain of conceptual systems, namely, the mathematical, is
regarded as the best way to grasp it.
Thus we have before us a development that proceeds with inward
regularity. In the first epoch, man beheld god and world, but god in the
world and the world in god: the one-ness, unity. In the second epoch,
man in fact beheld soul and body, man and nature; the soul as bearer of
the living Logos, the bearer of what is not born and does not die;
nature as what is born and dies. In the third phase man has ascended to
the abstract contrast of subject (himself) and object ( the external
world.) The object is something so robust that man no longer even
attempts to throw light on it with concepts. It is experienced as
something alien to man, something that is examined from outside with
mathematics although mathematics cannot penetrate into the inner
essence. For this reason, Cusanus applied mathematics only symbolically,
and timidly at that.
The striving to develop science must therefore be pictured as
emerging from earlier faculties of mankind. A time had to come when this
science would appear. It had to develop the way it did. We can follow
this if we focus clearly on the three phases of development that I have
just described.
We see how the first phase extends to the Eighth Century B.C. to the
ancient sage of Southern Europe whom I have described today. The second
extends from him to Nicholas Cusanus. We find ourselves in the third
phase now. The first is pneumatological, directed to the spirit in its
primeval form. The second is mystical, taking the world in the broadest
sense possible. The third is mathematical. Considering the significant
characteristics, therefore, we trace the first phase — ancient
pneumatology — as far as the ancient Southern wise man. Magical
mysticism extends from there to Meister Eckhart and Nicholas Cusanus.
The age of mathematizing natural science proceeds from Cusanus into our
own time and continues further. More on this tomorrow.
∴
Lecture III
26 December 1922, Dornach
In the last two lectures I tried to indicate the point in time when
the scientific outlook and manner of thinking, such as we know it today,
arose in the course of time. It was pointed out yesterday that the whole
character of this scientific thinking, emerging at the beginning most
clearly in Copernicus' conception of astronomy, depends on the way
in which mathematical thinking was gradually related to the reality of
the external world. The development of science in modern times has been
greatly affected by a change — one might almost say a
revolutionary change — in human perception in regard to
mathematical thinking itself. We are much inclined nowadays to ascribe
permanent and absolute validity to our own manner of thinking.
Nobody notices how much matters have changed. We take a certain
position today in regard to mathematics and to the relationship of
mathematics to reality. We assume that this is the way it has to be and
that this is the correct relationship. There are debates about it from
time to time, but within certain limits this is regarded as the true
relationship. We forget that in a none too distant past mankind felt
differently concerning mathematics. We need only recall what happened
soon after the point in time that I characterized as the most important
in modern spiritual life, the point when Nicholas Cusanus presented his
dissertation to the world. Shortly after this, not only did Copernicus
try to explain the movements of the solar system with mathematically
oriented thinking of the kind to which we are accustomed today, but
philosophers such as Descartes and Spinoza [24] began to apply this mathematical thought to
the whole physical and spiritual universe.
Even in such a book as his Ethics, the philosopher Spinoza
placed great value on presenting his philosophical principles and
postulates, if not in mathematical formulae — for actual
calculations play no special part — yet in such a manner that the
whole form of drawing conclusions, of deducing the later rules from
earlier ones, is based on the mathematical pattern. By and by it
appeared self-evident to the men of that time that in mathematics they
had the right model for the attainment of inward certainty. Hence they
felt that if they could express the world in thoughts arranged in the
same clear-cut architectural order as in a mathematical or geometrical
system, they would thereby achieve something that would have to
correspond to reality. If the character of scientific thinking is to be
correctly understood, it must be through the special way in which man
relates to mathematics and mathematics relates to reality. Mathematics
had gradually become what I would term a self-sufficient inward capacity
for thinking. What do I mean by that?
The mathematics existing in the age of Descartes
[25] and Copernicus can certainly be described
more or less in the same terms as apply today. Take a modern
mathematician, for example, who teaches geometry, and who uses his
analytical formulas and geometrical concepts in order to comprehend some
physical process. As a geometrician, this mathematician starts from the
concepts of Euclidean geometry, the three-dimensional space (or merely
dimensional space, if he thinks of non-Euclidean geometry.)
[26] In three-dimensional space he
distinguishes three mutually perpendicular directions that are otherwise
identical. Space, I would say, is a self-sufficient form that is simply
placed before one's consciousness in the manner described above without
questions being raised such as: Where does this form come from? Or,
Where do we get our whole geometrical system?
In view of the increasing superficiality of psychological thinking,
it was only natural that man could no longer penetrate to those inner
depths of soul where geometrical thought has its base. Man takes his
ordinary consciousness for granted and fills this consciousness with
mathematics that has been thought-out but not experienced. As an example
of what is thought-out but not experienced, let us consider the three
perpendicular dimensions of Euclidean space. Man would have never
thought of these if he had not experienced a threefold orientation
within himself. One orientation that man experiences in himself is from
front to back. We need only recall how, from the external modern
anatomical and physiological point of view, the intake and excretion of
food, as well as other processes in the human organism, take place from
front to back. The orientation of these specific processes differs from
the one that prevails when, for example, I do something with my right
arm and make a corresponding move with my left arm. Here, the processes
are oriented left and right. Finally, in regard to the last orientation,
man grows into it during earthly life. In the beginning he crawls on all
fours and only gradually, stands upright, so that this last orientation
flows within him from above downward and up from below.
As matters stand today, these three orientations in man are regarded
very superficially. These processes — front to back, right to left
or left to right, and above to below — are not inwardly
experienced so much as viewed from outside. If it were possible to go
back into earlier ages with true psychological insight, one would
perceive that these three orientations were inward experiences for the
men of that time. Today our thoughts and feelings are still halfway
acknowledged as inward experiences, but he man of a bygone age had a
real inner experience, for example, of the front-to-back orientation. He
had not yet lost awareness of the decrease in intensity of taste
sensations from front to back in the oral cavity. The qualitative
experience that taste was strong on the tip of the tongue, then grew
fainter and fainter as it receded from front to back, until it
disappeared entirely, was once a real and concrete experience. The
orientation from front to back was felt in such qualitative experiences.
Our inner life is no longer as intense as it once was. Therefore, today,
we no longer have experiences such as this. Likewise man today no longer
has a vivid feeling for the alignment of his axis of vision in order to
focus on a given point by shifting the right axis over the left. Nor
does he have a full concrete awareness of what happens when, in the
orientation of right-left, he relates his right arm and hand to the left
arm and hand. Even less does he have a feeling that would enable him to
say: The thought illuminates my head and, moving in the direction from
above to below, it strikes into my heart. Such a feeling, such an
experience, has been lost to man along with the loss of all inwardness
of world experience. But it did once exist. Man did once experience the
three perpendicular orientation of space within himself. And these three
spatial orientations — right-left, front-back, and above-below
— are the basis of the three-dimensional framework of space, which
is only the abstraction of the immediate inner experience described
above.
So what can we say when we look back at the geometry of earlier
times? We can put it like this: It was obvious to a man in those ages
that merely because of his being human the geometrical elements revealed
themselves in his own life. By extending his own above-below,
right-left, and front-back orientations, he grasped the world out of his
own being.
Try to sense the tremendous difference between this mathematical
feeling bound to human experience, and the bare, bleak mathematical
space layout of analytical geometry, which establishes a point somewhere
in abstract space, draws three coordinating axes at right angles to each
other and thus isolates this thought-out space scheme from all living
experience. But man has in fact torn this thought-out spatial diagram
out of his own inner life. So, if we are to understand the origin of the
later mathematical way of thinking that was taken over by science, if we
are to correctly comprehend its self-sufficient presentation of
structures, we must trace it back to the self-experienced mathematics of
a bygone age. Mathematics in former times was something completely
different. What was once present in a sort of dream-like experience of
three-dimensionality and then became abstracted, exists today completely
in the unconscious. As a matter of fact, man even now produced
mathematics from his own three-dimensionality. But the way in which he
derives this outline of space from his experiences of inward orientation
is completely unconscious. None of this rises into consciousness except
the finished spatial diagram. The same is true of all completed
mathematical structures. They have all been severed from their roots. I
chose the example of the space scheme, but I could just as well mention
any other mathematical category taken from algebra or arithmetic. They
are nothing but schemata drawn from immediate human experience and
raised into abstraction.
Going back a few centuries, perhaps to the fourteenth century, and
observing how people conceived of things mathematical, we find that in
regard to numbers they still had an echo of inward feelings. In an age
in which numbers had already become an abstract ads they are today,
people would have been unable to find the names for numbers. The words
designating numbers are often wonderfully characteristic. Just think of
the word "two." (zwei) It clearly expresses a real process,
as when we say entzweien, "to cleave in twain." Even
more, it is related to zweifeln, "to doubt." It is
not mere imitation of an external process when the number two,
zwei, is described by the word Entzweien, which indicates
the disuniting, the splitting, of something formerly a whole. It is in
fact something that is inwardly experienced and only then made into a
scheme. It is brought up from within, just as the abstract
three-dimensional space-scheme is drawn up from inside the mind.
We arrive back at an age of rich spiritual vitality that still
existed in the first centuries of Christianity, as can be demonstrated
by the fact that mathematics, mathesis, and mysticism were considered to
be almost one and the same. Mysticism, mathesis, and mathematics are
one, though only in a certain connection. For a mystic of the first
Christian centuries, mysticism was something that one experienced more
inwardly in the soul. Mathematics was the mysticism that one experienced
more outwardly with the body; for example, geometry with the body's
orientations to front-and-back, right-and-left, and up-and-down. One
could say that actual mysticism was soul mysticism and that mathematics,
mathesis, was mysticism of the corporeality. Hence, proper mysticism was
inwardly experienced in what is generally understood by this term;
whereas mathesis, the other mysticism, as experienced by means of an
inner experience of the body, as yet not lost.
As a matter of fact, in regard to mathematics and the mathematical
method Descartes and Spinoza still had completely different feelings
from what we have today. Immerse yourself in these thinkers, not
superficially as in the practice today when one always wants to discover
in the thinkers of old the modern concepts that have been drilled into
our heads, but unselfishly, putting yourself mentally in their place.
You will find that even Spinoza still retained something of a mystical
attitude toward the mathematical method.
The philosophy of Spinoza differs from mysticism only in one
respect. A mystic like Meister Eckhart or Johannes Tauler
[27] attempts to
experience the cosmic secrets more in the depths of feeling. Equally
inwardly, Spinoza constructs the mysteries of the universe along
mathematical, methodical lines, not specifically geometrical lines, but
lines experienced mentally by mathematical methods. In regard to soul
configuration and mood, there is no basic difference between the
experience of Meister Eckhart's mystical method and Spinoza's
mathematical one. Anyone how makes such a distinction does not really
understand how Spinoza experienced his Ethics, for example, in a truly
mathematical-mystical way. His philosophy still reflects the time when
mathematics, mathesis, and mysticism were felt as one and the same
experience in the soul.
Now, you will perhaps recall how, in my book The Case for
Anthroposophy, [28] I tried to explain
the human organization in a way corresponding to modern thinking. I
divided the human organization — meaning the physical one —
into the nerve-sense system, the rhythmic system, and the metabolic-limb
system. I need not point out to you that I did not divide man into
separate members placed side by side in space, although certain academic
persons have accused [29] me of such a caricature. I made it clear that these
three systems interpenetrate each other. The nerve-sense system is
called the "head system" because it is centered mainly in
the head, but it spreads out into the whole body. The breathing and
blood rhythms of the chest system naturally extend into the head
organization, and so on. The division is functional, not local. An
inward grasp of this threefold membering will give you true insight into
the human being.
Let us now focus on this division for a certain purpose. To begin
with, let us look at the third member of the human organization, that of
digestion (metabolism) and the limbs. Concentrating on the most striking
aspect of this member, we see that man accomplishes the activities of
external life by connecting his limbs with his inner experiences. I have
characterized some of these, particularly the inward orientation
experience of the three directions of space. In his external movements,
in finding his orientation in the world, man's limb system achieves
inward orientation in the three directions. In walking, we place
ourselves in a certain manner into the experience of above-below. In
much that we do with our hands or arms, we bring ourselves into the
orientation of right-and-left. To the extent that speech is a movement
of the aeriform in man, we even fit ourselves into direction of
front-and-back, back-and-front, when we speak. Hence, in moving about in
the world, we place our inward orientation into the outer world.
Let us look at the true process, rather than the merely illusionary
one, in a specific mathematical case. It is an illusionary process,
taking place purely in abstract schemes of thought, when I find
somewhere in the universe a process in space, and I approach it as an
analytical mathematician in such a way that I draw or imagine the three
coordinate axes of the usual spatial system and arrange this external
process into Descartes' purely artificial space scheme.
This is what occurs above, in the realm of thought schemes, through
the nerve-sense system. One would not achieve a relationship to such a
process in space if it were not for what one does with one's limbs, with
one's whole body, if it were not for inserting oneself into the whole
world in accordance with the inward orientation of above-below,
right-left, and front-back. When I walk forward, I know that on one hand
I place myself in the vertical direction in order to remain upright. I
am also aware that in walking I adjust my direction to the back-to-front
orientation, and when I swim and use my arms, I orient myself in right
and left. I do not understand all this if I apply Descartes' space
scheme, the abstract scheme of the coordinate axes. What gives me the
impression of reality in dealing with matters of space is found only
when I say to myself: Up in the head, in the nerve system, an illusory
image arises of something that occurs deep down in the subconscious.
Here, where man cannot reach with his ordinary consciousness, something
takes place between his limb system and the universe. The whole of
mathematics, of geometry, is brought up out of our limb system of
movement. We would not have geometry if we did not place ourselves into
the world according to inward orientation. In truth, we geometrize when
we lift what occurs in the subconscious into the illusory of the thought
scheme. This is the reason why it appears so abstractly independent to
us. But his is something that this only come about in recent times. In
the age in which mathesis, mathematics, was still felt to be something
close to mysticism, the mathematical relationship to all things was also
viewed as something human.
Where is the human factor if I imagine an abstract point somewhere
in space crossed by three perpendicular directions and then apply this
scheme to a process perceived in actual space? It is completely divorced
from man, something quite inhuman. This non-human element, which has
appeared in recent times in mathematical thinking, was once human. But
when was it human?
The actual date has already been indicated, but the inner aspect is
still to be described. When was it human? It was human when man did not
only experience in his movements and his inward orientation in space
that he stepped forward from behind and moved in such a way that he was
aware of his vertical as well as the horizontal direction, but when he
also felt the blood's inward activity in all such moving about, in all
such inner geometry. There is always blood activity when I move forward.
Think of the blood activity present when, as an infant, I lifted myself
up from the horizontal to an upright position! Behind man's movements,
behind his experience of the world by virtue of movements, (which can
also be, and at one time was, an inward experience) there stands the
experience of the blood. Every movement, small or large, that I
experience as I perform it contains its corresponding blood experience.
Today blood is to us the red fluid that seeps out when we prick our
skin. We can also convince ourselves intellectually of its existence.
But in the age when mathematics, mathesis, was still connected with
mysticism, when in a dreamy way the experience of movement was inwardly
connected with that of blood, man was inwardly aware of the blood. It
was one thing to follow the flow of blood through the lungs and quite
another to follow it through the head. Man followed the flow of the
blood in lifting his knee or his foot, and he inwardly felt and
experienced himself through and through in his blood. The blood has one
tinge when I raise my foot, another when I place it firmly on the
ground. When I lounge around and doze lazily, the blood's nuance differs
from the one it has when I let thoughts shoot through my head. The whole
person can take on a different form when, in addition to the experience
of movement, he has that of the blood. Try to picture vividly what I
mean. Imagine that you are walking slowly, one step at a time; you begin
to walk faster; you start to run, to turn yourself, to dance around.
Suppose that you were doing all this, not with today's abstract
consciousness, but with inward awareness: You would have a different
blood experience at each stage, with the slow walking, then the increase
in speed, the running, the turning, the dancing. A different nuance
would be noted in each case. If you tried to draw this inner experience
of movement, you would perhaps have to sketch it like this (white line.)
But for each position in which you found yourself during this experience
of movement, you would draw a corresponding inward blood experience
(red, blue, yellow — see Figure 2)
Figure 2
Of the first experience, that of movement, you would say that you
have it in common with external space, because you are constantly
changing your position. The second experience, which I have marked by
means of the different colors, is a time experience, a sequence of inner
intense experiences.
In fact, if you run in a triangle, you can have one inner experience
of the blood. You will have a different one if you run in a square.
What is outwardly quantitative and geometric, is inwardly intensely
qualitative in the experience of the blood.
It is surprising, very surprising, to discover that ancient
mathematics spoke quite differently about the triangle and the square.
Modern nebulous mystics describe great mysteries, but there is no great
mystery here. It is only what a person would have experienced inwardly
in the blood when he walked the outline of a triangle or a square, not
to mention the blood experience corresponding to the pentagram. In the
blood the whole of geometry becomes qualitative inward experience. We
arrive back at a time when one could truly say, as Mephistopheles does
in Goethe's Faust, "Blood is a very special fluid."
[30] This is
because, inwardly experienced, the blood absorbs all geometrical forms
and makes of them intense inner experiences. Thereby man learns to know
himself as well. He learns to know what it means to experience a
triangle, a square, a pentagram; he becomes acquainted with the
projection of geometry on the blood and its experiences. This was once
mysticism. Not only was mathematics, mathesis, closely related to
mysticism, it was in fact the external side of movement, of the limbs,
while the inward side was the blood experience. For the mystic of bygone
times all of mathematics transformed itself out of a sum of spatial
formations into what is experienced in the blood, into an intensely
mystical rhythmic inner experience.
We can say that once upon a time man possessed a knowledge that he
experienced, that he was an integral part of; and that at the point in
time that I have mentioned, he lost this oneness of self with the world,
this participation in the cosmic mysteries. He tore mathematics loose
from his inner being. No longer did he have the experience of movement;
instead, he mathematically constructed the relationships of movement
outside. He no longer had the blood experience; the blood and its rhythm
became something quite foreign to him. Imagine what this implies: Man
tears mathematics free from his body and it becomes something abstract.
He loses his understanding of the blood experience. Mathematics no
longer goes inward. Picture this as a soul mood that arose at a specific
time. Earlier, the soul had a different mood than later. Formerly, it
sought the connection between blood experience and experience of
movement; later, it completely separated them. It no longer related the
mathematical and geometrical experience to its own movement. It lost the
blood experience. Think of this as real history, as something that
occurs in the changing moods of evolution. Verily, a man who lived in
the earlier age, when mathesis was still mysticism, put his whole soul
into the universe. He measured the cosmos against himself. He lived in
astronomy.
Modern man inserts his system of coordinates into the universe and
keeps himself out of it. Earlier, man sensed a blood experience with
each geometrical figure. Modern man feels no blood experience; he loses
the relationship to his own heart, where the blood experiences are
centered. Is it imaginable that in the seventh or eighth century, when
the soul still felt movement as a mathematical experience and blood as a
mystical experience, anybody would have founded a Copernican astronomy
with a system of coordinates simply inserted into the universe and
totally divorced from man? No, this became possible only when a specific
soul constitution arose in evolution. And after that something else
became possible as well. The inward blood awareness was lost. Now the
time had come to discover the movements of the blood externally through
physiology and anatomy. Hence you have this change in evolution: On one
hand Copernican astronomy, on the other the discovery of the circulation
of the blood by Harvey,
[31] a contemporary of
Bacon and Hobbes. A world view gained by abstract mathematics cannot
produce anything like the ancient Ptolemaic theory, which was
essentially bound up with man and the living mathematics he experienced
within himself. Now, one experiences an abstract system of coordinates
starting with an arbitrary zero point. No longer do we have the inward
blood experience; instead, we discover the physical circulation of the
blood with the heart in the center.
The birth of science thus placed itself into the whole context of
evolution in both its conscious and unconscious processes. Only in this
way, out of the truly human element, can one understand what actually
happened, what had to happen in recent times for science — so
self-evident today — to come into being in the first place. Only
thus could it even occur to anybody to conduct such investigations as
led, for example, to Harvey's discovery of the circulation of the blood.
We shall continue with this tomorrow.
∴
Lecture IV
27 December 1922, Dornach
In the last lecture, I spoke of a former view of life from which the
modern scientific view has evolved. It still combined the qualitative
with the form-related or geometrical elements of mathematics, the
qualitative with the quantitative. One can therefore look back at a
world conception in which the triangle or another geometrical form was
an inner experience no matter whether the form referred to the surface
of a given body or to its path of movement. Geometrical and arithmetical
forms were intensely qualitative inner experiences. For example, a
triangle and a square were each conceived as emerging from a specific
inward experience.
This conception could change into a different one only when men lost
their awareness that everything quantitative — including
mathematics — is originally experienced by man in direct
connection with the universe. It changed when the point was reached
where the quantitative was severed from what man experiences. We can
determine this moment of separation precisely. It occurred when all
concepts of space that included man himself were replaced by the
schematic view of space that is customary today, according to which,
from an arbitrary starting point, the three coordinates are drawn. The
kind of mathematics prevalent today, by means of which man wants to
dominate the so-called phenomena of nature, arose in this form only
after it had been separated from the human element. Expressing it more
graphically, I would say in a former age man perceived mathematics as
something that he experienced within himself together with his god or
gods, whereby the god ordered the world. It came as no surprise
therefore to discover this mathematical order in the world. In contrast
to this, to impose an arbitrary space outline or some other mathematical
formula on natural phenomena — even if such abstract mathematical
concepts can be identified with significant aspects in these so-called
natural phenomena — is a procedure that cannot be firmly related
to human experiences. Hence, it cannot be really understood and is at
most simply assumed to be a fact. Therefore in reality it cannot be an
object of any perception. The most that can be said of such an
imposition of mathematics on natural phenomena is that what has first
been mathematically thought out is then found to fit the phenomena of
nature. But why this is so can no longer be discovered within this
particular world perception.
Think back to the other worldview that I have previously described
to you, when all corporeality was regarded as image of the spirit. One
looking at a body found in it the image of spirit. One then looked back
on oneself, on what — in union with one's own divine nature
— one experienced as mathematics through one's own bodily
constitution. As a work of art is not something obscure but is
recognized as the image of the artist's ideas, so one found in corporeal
nature the mathematical images of what one had experienced with one's
own divine nature. The bodies of external nature were images of the
divine spiritual. The instant that mathematics is separated from man and
is regarded only as an attribute of bodies that are no longer seen as a
reflection of spirit, in that instant agnosticism creeps into
knowledge.
Take a concrete example, the first phenomenon that confronts us
after the birth of scientific thinking, the Copernican system. It is not
my intention today or in any of these lectures to defend either the
Ptolemaic or the Copernican system. I am not advocating either one. I am
only speaking of the historical fact that the Copernican system has
replaced the Ptolemaic. What I say today does not imply that I favor the
old Ptolemaic system over the Copernican. But this must be said as a
matter of history. Imagine yourself back in the age when man experienced
his own orientation in space: above-below, right-left, front-back. He
could experience this only in connection with the earth. He could, for
example, experience the vertical orientation in himself only in relation
to the direction of gravity. He experienced the other two in connection
with the four compass points according to which the earth itself is
oriented. All this he experienced together with the earth as he
felt himself standing firmly on it. He thought of himself not just as a
being that begins with the head and ends a the sole of the feet. Rather,
he felt himself penetrated by the force of gravity, which had something
to do with his being but did not cease at the soles of his feet. Hence,
feeling himself within the nature of the gravitational force, man felt
himself one with the earth. For his concrete experience, the starting
point of his cosmology was thus given by the earth. Therefore he felt he
Ptolemaic system to be justified.
Only when man severed himself from mathematics, only then was it
possible also to sever mathematics from the earth and to found an
astronomical system with its center in the sun. Man had to lose the old
experience-within-himself before he could accept a system with its
center outside the earth. The rise of the Copernican system is therefore
intimately bound up with the transformation of civilized mankind's soul
mood. The origin of modern scientific thinking cannot be separated from
the general mental and soul condition, but must be viewed in context
with it.
It is only natural that statements like this are considered absurd
by our contemporaries, who believe in the present world view far more
fervently than the sectarians of olden days believed in their dogmas.
But to give the scientific mode of thinking its proper value, it must be
seen as arising inevitably out of human nature and evolution. In the
course of these lectures, we shall see that by doing this we are
actually assigning far greater value to science than do the modern
agnostics.
Thus the Copernican world conception came into being, the projection
of the cosmic center from the earth to the sun. Fundamentally, the whole
cosmic thought edifice of Giordano Bruno, [32] who was
born in 1548 and burned at the stake in Rome in 1600, was already
contained in the Copernican world view. It is often said that Giordano
Bruno glorifies the modern view of nature, glorifies Copernicanism. One
must have deep insight into the inner necessity with which this new
cosmology arose if one is to have any feeling at all for the manner and
tone in which Giordano Bruno speaks and writes. Then one sees that
Giordano Bruno does not sound like the followers of the new view or like
the stragglers of the old view. He really does not speak about the
cosmos mathematically so much as lyrically. There is something musical
in the way Giordano Bruno describes the modern conception of nature. Why
is that? The reason is that Giordano Bruno, though he was rooted with
his whole soul in a bygone world perception, told himself with his
outward intellect: The way things have turned out in history, we cannot
but accept the Copernican world picture. He understood the absolute
necessity that had been brought about by evolution. This Copernican
world view, however, was not something he had worked out for himself. It
was something given to him, and which he found appropriate for his
contemporaries. Belonging as he did to an older world conception, he
could not help but experience inwardly what he had to perceive and
accept as knowledge. He still had the faculty of inner experience, but
he did not have scientific forms for it. Therefore although he described
them so wonderfully, he did not follow the Copernican directions of
thought in the manner of Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, or Newton. [33] Instead,
he tried to experience the cosmos in the old way, the way that was
suitable when the world cosmos was experienced within one's being. But
in order to do this, mathematics would have had to be also mysticism,
inward experience, in the way I described yesterday. This it could not
be for Giordano Bruno. The time for it was past. Hence, his attempt to
enter the new cosmology through living experience became an experience,
not of knowledge but of poetry, or at least partially so. This fact
lends Giordano's works their special coloring. The atom is still a
monad; in his writings, it is still something alive. The sum of cosmic
laws retains a soul quality, but not because he experienced the soul in
all the smallest details as did the ancient mystics, and not because he
experienced the mathematical laws of the cosmos as the intentions of the
spirit. No, it was because he roused himself to wonder at this new
cosmology and to glorify it poetically in a pseudo-scientific form.
Giordano Bruno is truly something like a connecting link between two
world conceptions, the present one and the ancient one that lasted into
the fifteenth century. Man today can form scarcely any idea of the
latter. All cosmic aspects were then still experienced by man, who did
not yet differentiate between the subject within himself and the cosmic
object outside. The two were still as one; man did not speak of the
three dimensions in space, sundered from the orientation within his own
body and appearing as above-below, right-left, and forward-backward.
Copernicus tried to grasp astronomy with abstract mathematical
ideas. On the other hand, Newton shows mathematics completely on its
own. Here I do not mean single mathematical deductions, but mathematical
thinking in general, entirely divorced from human experience. This
sounds somewhat radical and objections could certainly be made to what I
am thus describing in broad outlines, but this does not alter the
essential facts. Newton is pretty much the first to approach the
phenomena of nature with abstract mathematical thinking. Hence, as a
kind of successor to Copernicus, Newton becomes the real founder of
modern scientific thinking.
It is interesting to see in Newton's time and in the age that
followed how civilized humanity is at pains to come to terms with the
immense transformation in soul configuration that occurred as the old
mathematical-mystical view gave way to the new mathematical-scientific
style. The thinkers of the time find it difficult to come to terms with
this revolutionary change. It becomes all the more evident when we look
into the details, the specific problems with which some of these people
wrestled. See how Newton, for instance, presents his system by trying to
relate it to the mathematics that has been severed from man. We find
that he postulates time, place, space, and motion. He says in effect in
his Principa: I need not define place, time, space, and motion
because everybody understands them. [34] Everybody knows what time is, what space, place,
and motion are, hence these concepts, taken from common experience, can
be used in my mathematical explanation of the universe. People are not
always fully conscious of what they say. In life, it actually happens
seldom that a person fully penetrates everything he says with his
consciousness. This is true even among the greatest thinkers. Thus
Newton really does not know why he takes place, time, space, and motion
as his starting points and feels no need to explain or define them,
whereas in all subsequent deductions he is at pains to explain and
define everything. Why does he do this? The reasons is that in regard to
place, time, motion, and space all cleverness and thinking avail us
nothing. No matter how much we think about these concepts, we grow no
wiser than we were to begin with. Their nature is such that we
experience them simply through our common human nature and must take
them as they come. A successor of Newton's, Bishop Berkeley,
[35] took
particular notice of this point. He was involved in philosophy more than
Newton was, but Berkeley illustrates the conflicts taking place during
the emergence of scientific thinking. In other respects, as we shall
presently hear, he was not satisfied with Newton, but he was especially
struck by the way that Newton took these concepts as his basis without
any explanation, that he merely said: I start out from place, time,
space, and motion; I do not define them; I take them as premises for my
mathematical and scientific reflections. Berkeley agrees that one must
do this. One must take these concepts in the way they are understood by
the simplest person, because there they are always clear. They become
unclear not in outward experience, but in the heads of metaphysicians
and philosophers. Berkeley feels that when these four concepts are found
in life, they are clear; but they are always obscure when found in the
heads of thinkers.
It is indeed true that all thinking about these concepts is of no
avail. One feels this. Therefore, Newton is only beginning to juggle
mathematically when he uses these concepts to explain the world. He is
juggling with ideas. This is not meant in a derogatory way; I only want
to describe Newton's abilities in a telling manner. One of the concepts
thus utilized by Newton is that of space. He manipulates the idea of
space as perceived by the man in the street. Still, a vestige of living
experience is contained therein. If, on the other hand, one pictures
space in terms of Cartesian mathematics, without harboring any
illusions, it makes one's brain reel. There is something undefinable
about this space, with its arbitrary center of coordinates. One can, for
example, speculate brilliantly (and fruitlessly) about whether
Descartes' space if finite or infinite. Ordinary awareness of
space that is still connected with the human element really is not at
all concerned with finiteness or infinity. It is after all quite without
interest to a living world conception whether space can be pictured as
finite or infinite. Therefore one can say that Newton takes the trivial
idea of space just as he finds it, but then he begins to mathematize.
But, due to the particular quality of thinking in his age, he already
has the abstracted mathematics and geometry, and therefore he penetrates
spatial phenomena and processes of nature with abstract mathematics.
Thereby he sunders the natural phenomena from man. In fact, in Newton's
physics we meet for the first time ideas of nature that have been
completely divorced from man. Nowhere in earlier times were conceptions
of nature so torn away from man as they are in Newtonian physics.
Going back to a thinker of the fourth or fifth century A.D. —
though people of that period can hardly be called
"thinkers," because their inner life was far more alive than
the mere life in thoughts — we would find that he held the view:
"I live; I experience space along with my God, and orient myself
in space up-and-down, right-left, and forward-backward, but I dwell in
space together with my God. He outlines the directions and I experience
them." So it was for a thinker of the third or fourth century A.D.
and even later; indeed, it only became different in the fourteenth
century. Thinking geometrically about space, man did not merely draw a
triangle but was conscious of the fact that, while he did this, God
dwelled within him and drew along with him. His experience was
qualitative; he drew the qualitative reality that God Himself had placed
within him. Everywhere in the outer world, whenever mathematics was
observed, the intentions of God were also observed.
By Newton's time mathematics has become abstracted. Man has
forgotten that originally he received mathematics as an inspiration from
God. And in this utterly abstract form, Newton now applies mathematics
to the study of space. As he writes his Principia, he simply applies
this abstracted mathematics, this idea of space (which he does not
define,) because he has a dim feeling that nothing will be gained by
trying to define it. He takes the trivial idea of space and applies his
abstract mathematics to it, thus severing it from any inward
experiences. This is how he speaks of the principles of nature.
Later on, interestingly enough, Newton goes somewhat deeper. This is
easy to see if one is familiar with his works. Newton becomes ill at
ease, as it were, when he contemplates his own view of space. He is not
quite comfortable with this space, torn as it is out of man and
estranged completely from the spirit. So he defines it after all, saying
that space is the sensorium of God. It is most interesting that at the
starting point of modern science the very person who was the first to
completely mathematize and separate space from man, eventually defines
space as God's sensorium,
[36] a
sort of brain or sense organ of God. Newton had torn nature asunder into
space and man-who-experiences-space. Having done this, he feels inwardly
uneasy when he views this abstract space, which man had formerly
experienced in union with his god. Formerly, man had said to himself:
What my human sensorium experiences in space, I experience together with
my god. Newton becomes uneasy, now that he has torn space away form the
human sensorium. He has thereby torn himself away from his permeation
with the divine-spiritual. Space, with all is mathematics, was not
something external. So, in later life, Newton addresses it as God's
sensorium, though to begin with he had torn the whole apart, thus
leaving space devoid of Spirit and God. But enough feeling remained in
Newton that he could not leave this externalized space devoid of God. So
he deified it again.
Scientifically, man tore himself loose from his god, and thus from
the spirit; but outwardly he again postulated the same spirit. What
happened here explains why a man like Goethe found it impossible
[37] to go along with
Newton on any point. Goethe's Theory of Color is one particularly
characteristic point. This whole procedure of first casting out the
spirit, separating it from man, was foreign to Goethe's nature. Goethe
always had the feeling that man has to experience everything, even what
is related to the cosmos. Even in regard to the three dimensions Goethe
felt that the cosmos was only a continuation of what man had inwardly
experienced. Therefore Goethe was by nature Newton's adversary.
Now let us return to Berkeley, who was somewhat younger than Newton,
but still belonged to the period of conflict that accompanied the rise
of the scientific way of thinking. Berkeley had no quarrel with Newton's
accepting the trivial ideas of place, space, time, and motion. But he
was not happy with this whole science that was emerging, and
particularly not with its interpretations of natural phenomena. It was
evident to him that when nature is utterly severed from man it cannot be
experienced at all, and that man is deceiving himself when he imagines
that he is experiencing it.
Therefore, Berkeley declared that bodies forming the external basis
for sense perceptions do not really exist. Reality is spiritual through
and through. The universe, as it appears to us — even where it
appears in a bodily form — is but the manifestation of an
all-pervading spirit. In Berkeley, these ideas appear pretty much as
mere assertions, for he no longer had any trace of the old mysticism and
even less of the ancient pneumatology. Except for his religious dogma,
he really had no ground at all for his assertion of such all-pervading
spirituality. But assert it he did, and so vigorously that all
corporeality become for him no more than a revelation of the spirit.
Hence it was impossible for Berkeley to say: I behold a color and there
is vibrating movement back of it that I cannot see — which is what
modern science justifiably states. Instead, Berkeley said: I cannot
hypothetically assume that there is anything possessing any corporeal
property such as vibratory movement. The basis of the physical world of
phenomena must be spiritually conceived. Something spiritual is behind a
color perception as its cause, which I experience in myself when I know
myself as spirit. Thus Berkeley is a spiritualist in the sense in which
this term is used in German philosophy.
For dogmatic reasons, but with a certain justification, Berkeley
makes innumerable objections against the assumption that nature can be
comprehended by mathematics that has been abstracted from direct
experience. Since to Berkeley the whole cosmos was spiritual, he also
viewed mathematics as having been formed together with the spirit of the
cosmos. He held that we do in fact experience the intentions of the
cosmic spirit insofar as they have mathematical forms, for that we
cannot apply mathematical concepts in an external manner to corporeal
objects.
In accordance with this point of view, Berkeley opposed what
mathematics had become for both Newton and Leibnitz,
[38] namely differential and integral calculus. Please,
do not misunderstand me. Today's lecture must be fashioned in such a way
that it cannot but provoke many objections in one who holds to the views
prevailing today. But these objections will fade away during the
ensuring lectures, if one is willing to keep an open mind. Today,
however, I want to present the themes that will occupy us in a rather
radical form.
Berkeley became an opponent of the whole infinitesimal calculus
[39] to the extent that it was then
known. He opposed what was beyond experience. In this regard, Berkeley's
feeling for things was often more sensitive than his thoughts. He felt
how, to the quantities that the mind could conceive, the emergence of
infinitesimal calculus added other quantities; namely, the
differentials, which attain definition only in the differential
coefficient. Differentials must be conceived in such a way that they
always elude our thinking, as it were. Our thinking refuses to
completely permeate them. Berkeley regarded this as a loss of reality,
since knowledge for him was only what could be experienced. Therefore he
could not approve of mathematical ideas that produced the
indetermination of the differentials.
What are we really doing when we seek differential equations for
natural phenomena? We are pointing to something that eludes our possible
experience. I realize, of course, that many of you cannot quite follow
me on these points, but I cannot here expound the whole nature of
infinitesimal calculus. I only want to draw attention to some aspects
that will contribute to our study of the birth of modern science.
Modern science set out to master the natural phenomena by means of a
mathematics detached from man, a mathematics no longer inwardly
experienced. By adopting this abstract mathematical view and these
concepts divorced from man, science arrived at a point where it could
examine only the inanimate. Having taken mathematics out of the sphere
of live experience, one can only apply it to what is dead. Therefore,
owing to this mathematical approach, modern science is directed
exclusively to the sphere of death. In the universe, death manifests
itself in disintegration, in atomization, in reduction to microscopic
parts — putting it simply, in a crumbling into dust. This is the
direction taken by the present-day scientific attitude. With a
mathematics detached from all living experience, it takes hold of
everything in the cosmos that turns to dust, that atomizes. From this
moment onward it becomes possible to dissipate mathematics itself into
differentials. We actually kill all living forms of thought, if we try
to penetrate them with any kind of differential equation, with any
differential line of thought. To differentiate is to kill; to integrate
is to piece the dead together again in some kind of framework, to fit
the differentials together again into a whole. But they do not thereby
become alive again, after having been annihilated. One ends up with dead
specters, not with anything living.
This is how the whole perspective of what was opening up through
infinitesimal calculus appeared to Berkeley. Had he expressed himself
concretely, he might well have said: First you kill the whole world by
differentiating it; then you fit its differentials together again in
integrals, but you no longer have a world, only a copy, an illusion.
With regard to its content, every integral is really an illusion, and
Berkeley already felt this to be so. Therefore, differentiation really
implies annihilation, while integration is the gathering up of bones and
dust, so that the earlier forms of the slain beings can be pieced
together again. But this does not bring them back to life; they remain
no more than dead replicas.
One can say that Berkeley's sentiments were untimely. This they
certainly were, for the new way of approach had to come. Anyone who
would have said that infinitesimal calculus should never have been
developed would have been called not a scientific thinker but a fool. On
the other hand, one must realize that at the outset of this whole stream
of development, feelings such as Berkeley's were understandable. He
shuddered at what he thought would come from a infinitesimal study of
nature and had to do with the process of birth but a study of all dying
aspects in nature.
Formerly this had not been observed, nor had there been any interest
in it. In earlier times, the coming-into-being, the germinating, had
been studied; now, one looked at all that was fading and crumbling into
dust. Man's conception was heading toward atomism, whereas previously it
had tended toward the continuous, lasting aspects of things. Since life
cannot exist without death and all living things must die, we must look
at and understand all that is dead in the world. A science of the
inanimate, the dead, had to arise. It was absolutely necessary. The time
that we are speaking about was the age in which mankind was ready for
such a science. But we must visualize how this went against the grain of
somebody who, like Berkeley, still lived completely in the old view.
The after-effects of what came into being then are still very much
with us today. We have witnessed the triumphs of just those scientific
labors that made Berkeley shudder. Until they were somewhat modified
through the modern theory of relativity,
[40] Newton's theories reigned supreme, Goethe's
revolt against them made no impression. For a true comprehension of what
went on we must go back to Newton's time and see the shuddering of
thinkers who still had a vivid recollection of earlier views and how
they clung to feelings that resembled the former ones.
Giordano Bruno shrank from studying the dead nature that was now to
be the object of study. He could not view it as dead in a purely
mathematical manner of thought, so he animated the atoms into monads and
imbued his mathematical thinking with poetry in order to retain it in a
personal sphere. Newton at first proceeded from a purely mathematical
standpoint, but then he wavered and defined space (which he has first
completely divorced from man through his external mathematics) as God's
sensorium. Berkeley in his turn rejected the new direction of thinking
altogether and with it the whole trend towards the infinitesimal.
Today, however, we are surrounded and overwhelmed by the world view
that Giordano Bruno tried to turn into poetry, that Newton felt
uncomfortable about, and that Berkeley completely rejected. Do we take
what Newton said — that space is a sensorium of God —
seriously when we think in the accepted scientific sense today? People
today like to regard as great thinkers those men who have said something
or other that they approve. But if the great men also said something
that they do not approve, they feel very superior and think:
Unfortunately, on this point he wasn't as enlightened as I am.
Thus many people consider Lessing
[41] a man of great
genius but make an exception for what he did toward the end of his life,
when he became convinced that we go through repeated earth lives.
Just because we must in the present age come to terms with the ideas
that have arisen, we must go back to their origin. Since mathematics has
once and for all been detached from man, and since nature has been taken
hold of by this abstract mathematics that has gradually isolated us from
the whole of nature, we must now somehow manage to find ourselves in
this nature. For we will not attain a coherent spiritual knowledge until
we once again have found the spirit in nature.
Just as it is a matter of course that every living man will sooner
or later die, so it was a matter of course that sooner or later in the
course of time a conception of death had to emerge from the former
life-imbued world view. Things that can only be learned from a corpse
cannot be learned by a person who is unwilling to examine the corpse.
Therefore certain mysteries of the world can be comprehended only if the
modern scientific way of thinking is taken seriously.
Let me close with a somewhat personal remark.
[42] The scientific world
view must be taken seriously, and for this reason I was never an
opponent of it; on the contrary, I regarded it as something that of
necessity belongs to our time. Often I had to speak out against
something that a scientist, or so-called scientist, had made of the
things that were discovered by unprejudiced investigation of the sphere
of death. It was the misinterpretation of such scientific discoveries
that I opposed. On this occasion let me state emphatically that I do not
wish to be regarded as in any way an opponent of the scientific
approach. I would consider it detrimental to all our anthroposophical
endeavors if a false opposition were to arise between what anthroposophy
seeks by way of spiritual research and what science seeks — and
must of necessity seek in its field — out of the modern
attitude.
I say this expressly, my dear friends, because a healthy discussion
concerning the relationship between anthroposophy and science must come
to pass within our movement. Anything that goes wrong in this respect
can only do grave harm to anthroposophy and should be avoided.
I mention this here because recently, in preparing these lectures, I
read in the anthroposophical periodical Die Drei that atomism was
being studied in a way in which no progress can be made. Therefore, I
want to make it clear that I consider all these polemics in Die
Drei about atomism as something that only serves to stultify the
relations between anthroposophy and science.
∴
Lecture V
28 December 1923, Dornach
The isolation of man's ideas (especially his mathematical ideas)
from his direct experience has proved to be the outstanding feature of
the spiritual development leading to modern scientific thinking. Let us
place this process once more before our mind's eye.
We were able to look back into ages past, when what man had to
acquire as knowledge of the world was experienced in communion with the
world. During those epochs, man inwardly did not experience his
threefold orientation — up-down, left-right, front-back — in
such a manner that he attributed it solely to himself. Instead, he felt
himself within the universal whole; hence, his own orientations were to
him synonymous with the three dimensions of space. What he pictured of
knowledge to himself, he experienced jointly with the world. Therefore,
with no uncertainty in his mind, he knew how to apply his concepts, his
ideas, to the world. This uncertainty has only arisen along with the
more recent civilization. We see it slowly finding its way into the
whole of modern thought and we see science developing under this
condition of uncertainty. This state of affairs must be clearly
recognized.
A few examples can illustrate what we are dealing with . Take a
thinker like John Locke, who lived from the seventeenth into the
eighteenth century. His writings show what an up-to-date thinker of his
age had to say concerning the scientific world perception. John Locke
[43] divided everything that man perceives in his
physical environment into two aspects. He divided the characteristic
features of bodies into primary and secondary qualities. Primary
qualities were those that he could only attribute to the objects
themselves, such as shape, position, and motion. Secondary qualities in
his view were those that did not actually belong to the external
corporeal things but were an effect that these objects had upon man.
Examples are color, sound, and warmth. Locke stated it thus: "When
I hear a sound, outside of me there is vibrating air. In a drawing, I
can picture these vibrations in the air that emanate from a
sound-aroused body and continue on into my ear. The shape that the
waves, as they are called, possess in the vibrating air can be pictured
by means of spatial forms. I can visualize their course in time —
all this, belonging to the primary qualities, certainly exists in the
external world, but it is silent, it is soundless. The quality of sound,
a secondary quality, only arises when the vibration of the air strikes
my ear, and with it arises that peculiar inner experience that I carry
within me as sound. It is the same with color, which is now lumped
together with light. There must be something out there in the world that
is somehow of a corporeal nature and somehow possesses shape and
movement. This exercises an effect on my eye and thus becomes my
experience of light or color. It is the same with the other things that
present themselves to my senses. The whole corporeal world must be
viewed like this; we must distinguish between the primary qualities in
it, which are objective, and the secondary qualities, which are
subjective and are the effects of the primary qualities upon
us."
Simply put, one could say with Locke that the external world outside
of man is form, position, and movement, whereas all that makes up the
content of the sense world exists in truth somehow inside us. The actual
content of color as a human experience is nowhere in the environment, it
lives in me. The actual content of sound is nowhere to be found outside,
it lives in me. The same is true of my experience of warmth or cold.
In former ages, when what had become the content of knowledge was
experienced jointly with the world, one could not possibly have had this
view because, as I have said, a man experienced mathematics by
participating in his own bodily orientation and placing this orientation
into his own movement. He experienced this, however, in communion with
the world. Therefore, his own experience was sufficient reason for
assuming the objectivity of position, place, and movement. Also, though
in another portion of his inner life, man again had this communion with
the world in regard to color, tone, and so forth. Just as the concept of
movement was gained through the experience of his own movement, so the
concept of color was gained through a corresponding internal experience
in the blood, and this experience was then connected with whatever is
warmth, color, sound, and so forth in the surrounding world. Certainly,
in earlier times, man distinguished position, location, movement, and
time-sequence from color, sound, and warmth, but these were
distinguished as being different kinds of experiences that were
undergone jointly with different kinds of existence in the objective
world.
Now, in the scientific age, the determination of place, movement,
position, and form ceased to be inward self-experience. Instead, they
were regarded as mere hypotheses that were caused by some external
reality. When the shape of a cannon is imagined, one can hardly say:
This form of the cannon is actually somehow within me. Therefore its
identification was directed outward and the imagined form of the cannon
was related to something objective. One could not very well admit that a
musket-ball was actually flying within one's brain; therefore, the
hypothetically thought-out movements were attributed to something
objective.
On the other hand, what one saw in the flying musket-ball, the flash
by which one perceived it and the sound by which one heart it, were
pushed into one's own human nature, since no other place could be found
for them. Man no longer knew how he experienced them jointly with the
objects; therefore, he associated them with his own being.
It actually took quite some time before those who thought along the
lines of the scientific age perceived the impossibility of this
arrangement. What had in fact taken place? The secondary qualities,
sound, color, and warmth experience, had become, as it were, fair game
in the world and, in regard to human knowledge, had to take refuge in
man. But before too long, nobody had any idea of how they lived there.
The experience, the self-experience, was no longer there. There was no
connection with external nature, because it was not experienced anymore.
Therefore these experiences were pushed into one's self. So far as
knowledge was concerned, they had, as it were, disappeared inside man.
Vaguely it was thought that an ether vibration out in space translated
itself into form and movement, and this had an effect on the eye, and
then worked on the optic nerve, and finally somehow entered the brain.
Our thoughts were a means of looking around inside for whatever it was
that, as an effect of the primary qualities, supposedly expressed itself
in man as secondary qualities. It took a long time, as I said, before a
handful of people firmly pointed out the oddity of these ideas. There is
something extraordinary in what the Austrian philosopher Richard Wahle
[44]
wrote in his Mechanism of Thinking, though he
himself did not realize the full implications of his sentence:
"Nihil est in cerebro, quod non est in nervis."
("There is nothing in the brain that is not in the nerves.")
It may not be possible with the means available today to examine the
nerves in every conceivable way, but even if we could we would not find
sound, color, or warmth experience in them. Therefore, they must not be
in the brain either. Actually, one has to admit now that they simply
disappear insofar as knowledge is concerned. One examines the
relationship of man to the world. Form, position, place, time, etc. are
beheld as objective. Sound, warmth, experience and color vanish; they
elude one. [45]
Finally, in the Eighteenth Century, this led Kant [46] to say that even the space and time
qualities of things cannot somehow be outside and beyond man. But there
had to be some relationship between man and the world. After all, such a
relationship cannot be denied if we are to have any idea of how man
exists together with the world. Yet, the common experience of man's
space and time relationships with the world simply did not exist
anymore. Hence arose the Kantian idea: If man is to apply mathematics,
for example, to the world, then it is his doing that he himself
makes the world into something mathematical. He impresses the whole
mathematical system upon the "things in themselves," which
themselves remain utterly unknown. — In the Nineteenth Century
science chewed on this problem interminably. The basic nature of man's
relation to cognition is simply this: uncertainty has entered into his
relationship with the world. He does not know how to recognize in the
world what he is experiencing. This uncertainty slowly crept into all of
modern thinking. We see it entering bit by bit into the spiritual life
of recent times.
It is interesting to place a recent example side by side with
Locke's thinking. August Weismann,
[47] a biologist of the
Nineteenth Century, conceived the thought: in any living organism, the
interplay of the organs (in lower organisms, the interaction of the
parts) must be regarded as the essential thing. This leads to
comprehension of how the organism lives. But in examining the organism
itself, in understanding it through the interrelationship of its parts,
we find no equivalent for the fact that the organism must die. If one
only observes the organism, so Weismann said, one finds nothing that
will explain death. In the living organism, there is absolutely nothing
that leads to the idea that the organism must die. For Weismann, the
only thing that demonstrates that an organism must die is the existence
of a corpse. This means that the concept of death is not gained from the
living organism. No feature, no characteristic, found in it indicates
that dying is a part of the organism. It is only when the event occurs,
when we find a corpse in the place of the living organism, that we know
the organism possesses the ability to die.
But, says Weismann, there is a class of organisms where corpses are
never found. These are the unicellular organisms. They only divide
themselves so there are no corpses. The propagation of such beings looks
like this:
One divides into two; each of these divides into two again, and so
on. There is never a corpse. Weismann therefore concludes that the
unicellular beings are immortal. This is the immortality of unicellular
beings that was famous in nineteenth-century biology. Why were these
organisms considered immortal? Because they never produce any corpses,
and because we cannot entertain the concept of death in the organic
realm as long as there are no corpses. Where there is no corpse, there
is no room for the concept of death. Hence, living beings that produce
no corpses are immortal.
This example shows how far man has removed himself in modern times
from any connection between the world and his thinking, his inner
experiences. His concept of an organism is no longer such that the fact
of its death can be perceived from it. This can only be deduced from the
existence of something like a corpse. Certainly, if a living organism is
only viewed from outside, if one cannot experience what is in it, then
indeed one cannot find death in the organism and an external sign is
necessary. But this only proves that in his thinking man feels himself
separated from the things around him.
From the uncertainty that has entered all thinking concerning the
corporeal world, from this divorce between our thoughts and our
experience, let us turn back to the time when self-experience still
existed. Not only did the inwardly experienced concept exist alongside
the externally excogitated concept of a triangle, square, or pentagram,
but there were also inwardly experienced concepts of blossoming and
fading, of birth and death. This inner experience of birth and death had
its gradations. When a child was seen to grow more and more animated,
when its face began to express its soul, when one really entered into
this growing process of the child, this could be seen as a continuation
of the process of birth, albeit a less pronounced and intensive one.
There were degrees in the experience of birth. When a man began to show
wrinkles and grey hair and grow feeble, this was seen as a first mild
degree of dying. Death itself was only the sum total of many less
pronounced death experiences, if I may use such a paradox. The concepts
of blossoming and decaying, of being born and dying, were inwardly
alive.
These concepts were experienced in communion with the corporeal
world. No line was drawn between man's self-experience and the events in
nature. Without a coastline, as it were, the inner land of man merged
into the ocean of the universe. Owing to this form of experience, man
lived himself into the world itself. Therefore, the thinkers of earlier
ages, whose ideas no longer receive proper attention from science, had
to form quite different ideas concerning something like what Weismann
called the "immortality of unicellular beings." What sort of
concept would an ancient thinker have formed had he had a microscope and
known something about the division of unicellular organisms? He would
have said: First I have the unicellular being; it divides itself into
two. Somewhat imprecisely, he might have said: It atomizes itself, it
divides itself; for a certain length of time, the two parts are
indivisible; then they divide again. As soon as division or atomization
begins, death enters in. He would not have derived death from the corpse
but from atomization, from the division into parts. His train of thought
would have been somewhat as follows: A being that is capable of life,
that is in the process of growth, is not atomized; and when the tendency
to atomization appears, the being dies. In the case of unicellular
beings, he would simply have thought that the two organisms cast off by
the first unicellular being were for the moment dead, but would be, so
to speak, revived immediately, and so forth. With atomization, with the
process of splitting, he would have linked the thought of death. If he
had known about unicellular beings and had seen one split into two, he
would not have thought that two new ones had come into being. On the
contrary, he would have said that out of the living monad, two atoms
have originated. Further, he would have said that wherever there is
life, wherever one observes life, one is not dealing with atoms. But if
they are found in a living being, then a proportionate part of the being
is dead. Where atoms are found, there is death, there is something
inorganic. This is how matters would have been judged in a former age
based on living inner knowledge of the world.
All this is not clearly described in our histories of philosophy,
although the discerning reader can have little doubt of it. The reason
is that the thought-forms of this older philosophy are totally unlike
today's thinking. Therefore anyone writing history nowadays is apt to
put his own modern concepts into the minds of earlier thinkers.
[48] But this is impermissible even with a
man as recent as Spinoza. In his book on what he justifiably calls
ethics, Spinoza follows a mathematical method but it is not mathematics
in the modern sense. He expounds his philosophy in a mathematical style,
joining idea to idea as a mathematician would. He still retains
something of the former qualitative experience of quantitative
mathematical concepts. Hence, even in contemplating the qualitative
aspect of man's inner life, we can say that his style is mathematical.
Today with our current concepts, it would be sheer nonsense to apply a
mathematical style to psychology, let alone ethics.
If we want to understand modern thinking, we must continually recall
this uncertainty, contrasting it to the certainty that existed in the
past but is no longer suited to our modern outlook. In the present phase
of scientific thinking, we have come to the point where this uncertainty
is not only recognized but theoretical justifications have been offered
for it. And example is a lecture given by the French thinker Henri
Poincaré [49] in 1912 on current ideas relating to matter. He speaks
of the existing controversy or debate concerning the nature of matter;
whether it should be thought of as being continuous or discrete; in
other words, whether one should conceive of matter as substantial
essence that fills space and is nowhere really differentiated in itself,
or whether substance, matter, is to be thought of as atomistic,
signifying more or less empty space containing within it minute
particles that by virtue of their particular interconnections form into
atoms, molecules, and so forth.
Aside from what I might call a few decorative embellishments
intended to justify scientific uncertainty, Poincaré's lecture
comes down to this: Research and science pass through various periods.
In one epoch, phenomena appear that cause the thinker to picture matter
in a continuous form, making it convenient to conceive of matter this
way and to focus on what shows up as continuity in the sense data. In a
different period the findings point more toward the concept of matter
being diffused into atoms, which are pictured as being fused together
again; i.e. matter is not continuous but discrete and atomistic.
Poincaré is of the opinion that always, depending on the
direction that research findings take, there will be periods when
thinking favors either continuity or atomism. He even speaks of an
oscillation between the two in the course of scientific development. It
will always be like this, he says, because the human mind has a tendency
to formulate theories concerning natural phenomena in the most
convenient way possible. If continuity prevails for a time, we get tired
of it. (These are not Poincaré's exact words, but they are close
to what he really intends.) Almost unconsciously, as it were, the human
mind then comes upon other scientific findings and begins to think
atomistically. It is like breathing where exhalation follows inhalation.
Thus there is a constant oscillation between continuity and atomism.
This merely results from a need of the human mind and according to
Poincaré, says nothing about the things themselves. Whether we
adopt continuity or atomism determines nothing about things themselves.
It is only our attempt to come to terms with the external corporeal
world.
It is hardly surprising that uncertainty should result from an age
which no longer finds self-experience in harmony with what goes on in
the world but regards it only as something occurring inside man. If you
no longer experience a living connection with the world, you cannot
experience continuity or atomism. You can only force your preconceived
notions of continuity or atomism on the natural phenomena. This
gradually leads to the suspicion that we formulate our theories
according to our changing needs. Just as we must breath in and out, so
we must, supposedly, think first continuistically for a while, then
atomistically for a while. If we always thought in the same way, we
would not be able to catch a breath of mental air. Thus our fatal
uncertainty is confirmed and justified. Theories begin to look like
arbitrary whims. We no longer live in any real connection with the
world. We merely think of various ways in which we might live with the
world, depending on our own subjective needs.
What would the old way of thought have said in such a case? It would
have said: In an age when the leading thinkers think continuistically,
they are thinking mainly of life. In one in which they think
atomistically, they are thinking primarily of death, of inorganic
nature, and they view even the organic in inorganic terms.
This is no longer unjustified arbitrariness. This rests on an
objective relationship to things. Naturally, I can take turns in dealing
with the animate and the inanimate. I can say that the very nature of
the animate requires that I conceive of it continuistically, whereas the
nature of the inanimate requires that I think of it atomistically. But I
cannot say that this is only due to the arbitrary nature of the human
mind. On the contrary, it corresponds to an objective relating of
oneself to the world. For such perception, the subjective aspect is
really disregarded, because one recognizes the animate in nature in
continual form and the inanimate in discrete form. And if one really has
to oscillate between the two forms of thought, this can be turned in an
objective direction by saying that one approach is suited to the living
and the other is suited to the dead. But there is no justification for
making everything subjective as Poincaré does. Nor is the
subjective valid for the way of perception that belonged to earlier
times.
The gist of this is that in the phase of scientific thinking
immediately preceding our own, there was a turn away from the animate to
the inanimate; i.e., from continuity to atomism. This was entirely
justified, if rightly understood. But, if we hope to objectively and
truly find ourselves in the world, we must find a way out of the dead
world of atomism, no matter how impressive it is as a theory. We must
get back to our own nature and comprehend ourselves as living beings. Up
to now, scientific development has tended in the direction of the
inanimate, the atomistic. When, in the first part of the Nineteenth
Century, this whole dreadful cell theory of Schleiden
[50] and Schwann [51] made its appearance, it did
not lead to continuity but to atomism. What is more, the scientific
world scarcely admitted this, nor has it to this day realized that it
should admit it since atomism harmonizes with the whole scientific
methodology. We were not aware that by conceiving the organism as
divided up into cells, we actually atomized it in our minds, which in
fact signifies killing it. The truth of the matter is that any real idea
of organisms has been lost to the atomistic approach.
This is what we can learn if we compare Goethe's views on organics
with those of Schleiden or the later botanists. In Goethe we find living
ideas that he actually experiences. The cell is alive, so the others are
really dealing with something organic, but the way they think is just as
though the cells were not alive but atoms. Of course, empirical research
does not always follow everything to its logical conclusion, and this
cannot be done in the case of the organic world. Our comprehension of
the organic world is not much aided by the actual observations resulting
from the cell theory. The non-atomistic somehow finds its way in, since
we have to admit that the cells are alive. But it is typical of many of
today's scientific discussions that the issues become confused and there
is no real clarity of thought.
In the night from New Year's Eve to New Year's Day
1922/23 the Goetheanum burned down. It was built in ten years, with the
help of various artists from many countries. This primarily wooden
building, in which each surface and corner was formed artistically (see
Steiner, Ways to a New Style in Architecture [London:
Anthroposophical Publishing Co. and New York: Anthroposophic Press,
1927]) had been designed in all details by Rudolf Steiner who also
managed the construction work through all these years. From the first of
January on, the activities had to be transferred into the so-called
"Schreinerei," a building that was used during the
construction of the Goetheanum. For the work itself, Rudolf Steiner did
not allow any interruption; the afternoon after the fire, the
"Three Kings Play" was performed, as was written on the
invitations of the ongoing course (see Christmas Plays from
Obervfer, trans. A.C. Harwood [London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1973]).
Rudolf Steiner introduced it with a short address, in which he spoke the
following words: "great suffering knows how to keep silent about
what it is feeling ... The building that was created in ten years
through the love and compassion of innumerable friends of the movement
was destroyed in one night. But just today the silent suffering
experiences what our friends have put in this work. Since we feel that
everything we do in our movement is necessary in our present
civilization, we will want to continue whatever we can in the given
frame, and therefore even in this hour as the flames outside still burn
and rise, although such suffering is present, still perform this play
which we promised our participants in connection with our course, and
which these participants expect. I also will hold the lecture I offered,
here in the 'Schreinerei' this evening at 8:00 P.M."
(printed in Ansprachen zu den Weihnachtsspielen aus Altem
Volkstum [Dornach: Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1974], GA Bibl. Nr. 274).
The beginning of the course's lecture was then devoted to the fire,
which is printed in The Younger Generation (Spring Valley, NY:
Anthroposophic Press, 1984).
The First Goetheanum Burning on the morning of January 1, 1923
In my last lecture, I said that one root of the scientific world
conception lay in the fact that John Locke and other thinkers of like
mind distinguished between the primary and secondary qualities of things
in the surrounding world. Locke called primary everything that pertains
to shape, to geometrical and numerical characteristics, to motion and to
size. From these he distinguished what he called the secondary
qualities, such as color, sound, and warmth. He assigned the primary
qualities to the things themselves, assuming that spatial corporeal
things actually existed and possessed properties such as form, motion
and geometrical qualities; and he further assumed that all secondary
qualities such as color, sound, etc. are only effects on the human
being. Only the primary qualities are supposed to be in the external
things. Something out there has size, form and motion, but is dark,
silent and cold. This produces some sort of effect that expresses itself
in man's experiences of sound, color and warmth.
I have also pointed out how, in this scientific age, space became an
abstraction in relation to the dimensions. Man was no longer aware that
the three dimensions — up-down, right-left, front-back —
were concretely experienced within himself. In the scientific age, he no
longer took this reality of the three dimensions into consideration. AS
far as he was concerned, they arose in total abstraction. He no longer
sought the intersecting point of the three dimensions where it is in
fact experienced; namely, within man's own being. Instead, he looked for
it somewhere in external space, wherever it might be. Thenceforth, this
space framework of the three dimensions had an independent existence,
but only an abstract thought-out one. This empty thought was no longer
experienced as belonging to the external world as well as to man;
whereas an earlier age experienced the three spatial dimensions in such
a way that man knew he was experiencing them not only in himself but
together with the nature of physical corporeality.
The dimensions of space had, as it were, already been abstracted and
ejected from man. They had acquired a quite abstract, inanimate
character. Man had forgotten that he experiences the dimensions of space
in his own being together with the external world; and the same applied
to everything concerned with geometry, number, weight, etc. He no longer
knew that in order to experience them in their full living reality, he
had to look into his own inner being. A man like John Locke transferred
the primary qualities — which are of like kind with the three
dimensions of space, the latter being a sort of form or shape —
into the external world only because the connection of these qualities
with man's inner being was no longer known.
The others, the secondary qualities, which were actually experienced
qualitatively (as color, tone, warmth, smell or taste,) now were viewed
as merely the effects of the things upon man, as inward experiences. But
I have pointed out that inside the physical man as well as inside the
etheric man these secondary qualities can no longer be found, so that
they became free-floating in a certain respect. They were no longer
sought in the outer world; they were relocated into man's inner being.
It was felt that so long as man did not listen to the world, did not
look at it, did not direct his sense of warmth to it, the world was
silent. It had primary qualities, vibrations that were formed in a
certain way, but no sound; it had processes of some kind in the ether,
but no color; it had some sort of processes in ponderable matter (matter
that has weight) — but it had no quality of warmth. As to these
experienced qualities, the scientific age was really saying that it did
not know what to do with them. It did not want to look for them in the
world, admitting that it was powerless to do so. They were sought for
within man, but only because nobody had any better ideas. To a certain
extent science investigates man's inner nature, but it does not (and
perhaps cannot) go very far with this, hence it really does not take
into consideration that these secondary qualities cannot be found in
this inner nature. Therefore it has no pigeonhole for them. Why is this
so?
Let us recall that if we really want to focus correctly on something
that is related to form, space, geometry or arithmetic, we have to turn
our attention to the inward life-filled activity whereby we build up the
spatial element within our own organism, as we do with above-below,
back-front, left-right. Therefore, we must say that if we want to
discover the nature of geometry and space, if we want to get to the
essence of Locke's primary qualities of corporeal things, we must look
within ourselves. Otherwise, we only attain to abstractions.
In the case of the secondary qualities such as sound, color, warmth,
smell and taste, man has to remember that his ego and astral body
normally dwell within his physical and etheric bodies but during sleep
they can also be outside the physical and etheric bodies. Just as man
experiences the primary qualities, such as the three dimensions, not
outside but within himself during full wakefulness, so, when he succeeds
(whether through instinct or through spiritual-scientific training) in
really inwardly experiencing what is to be found outside the physical
and etheric bodies from the moment of falling asleep to waking up, he
knows that he is really experiencing the true essence of sound, color,
smell, taste, and warmth in the external world outside his own body.
When, during the waking condition, man is only within himself, he cannot
experience anything but picture-images of the true realities of tone,
color, warmth, smell and taste. But these images correspond to
soul-spirit realities, not physical-etheric ones. In spite of the fact
that what we experience as sound seems to be connected with certain
forms of air vibrations, just as color is connected with certain
processes in the colorless external world, it still has to be recognized
that both are pictures, not of anything corporeal, but of the
soul-spirit element contained in the external world.
We must be able to tell ourselves: When we experience a sound, a
color, a degree of warmth, we experience an image of them. But we
experience them as reality, when we are outside our physical body. We
can portray the facts in a drawing as follows: Man experiences the
primary qualities within himself when fully awake, and projects them as
images into the outer world. If he only knows them in the outer world,
he has the primary qualities only in images (arrow in sketch). These
images are the mathematical geometrical, and arithmetical qualities of
things.
It is different in the case of the secondary qualities. (The
horizontal lines stand for the physical and etheric body of man, the red
shaded area for the soul-spirit aspect, the ego and astral body.) Man
experiences them outside his physical and etheric body,
[53] and projects only the images into himself. Because
the scientific age no longer saw through this, mathematical forms and
numbers became something that man looked for abstractly in the outer
world. The secondary qualities became something that man looked for only
in himself. But because they are only images in himself, man lost them
altogether as realities.
As few isolated thinkers, who still retained traditions of earlier
views concerning the outer world, struggled to form conceptions that
were truer to reality than those that, in the course of the scientific
age, gradually emerged as the official views. Aside from Paracelsus,
[54]
there was, for example, van Helmont, [55] who
was well aware that man's spiritual element is active when color, tone,
and so forth are experienced. During the waking state, however, the
spiritual is active only with the aid of the physical body. Hence it
produces only an image of what is really contained in sound or color.
This leads to a false description of external reality; namely, that
purely mathematical-mechanistic form of motion for what is supposed to
be experienced as secondary qualities in man's inner being, whereas, in
accordance with their reality, their true nature, they can only be
experienced outside the body. We should not be told that if we wish to
comprehend the true nature of sound, for example, we ought to conduct
physical experiments as to what happens in the air that carries us to
the sound that we hear. Instead, we should be told that if we want to
acquaint ourselves with the true nature of sound, we have to form an
idea of how we really experience sound outside our physical and etheric
bodies. But these are thoughts that never occurred to the men of the
scientific age. They had no inclination to consider the totality of
human nature, the true being of man. Therefore they did not find either
mathematics or the primary qualities in this unknown human nature; and
they did not find the secondary qualities in the external world, because
they did not know that man belongs to it also.
I do not say that one has to be clairvoyant in order to gain the
right insight into these matters, although a clairvoyant approach would
certainly produce more penetrating perceptions in this area. But I do
say that a healthy and open mind would lead one to place the primary
qualities, everything mathematical-mechanical, into man's inner being,
and to place the secondary qualities into the outer world. The thinkers
no longer understand human nature. They did not know how man's
corporeality is filled with spirit, or how this spirit, when it is awake
in a person, must forget itself and devote itself to the body if it is
to comprehend mathematics. Nor was it known that this same spirituality
must take complete hold of itself and live independently of the body,
outside the body, in order to come to the secondary qualities.
Concerning all these matters, I say that clairvoyant perception can give
greater insight, but it is not indispensable. A healthy and open mind
can feel that mathematics belongs inside, while sound, color, etc. are
something external.
In my notes on Goethe's scientific works
[56] in the 1880's, I set forth what healthy feeling can do
in this direction. I never mentioned clairvoyant knowledge, but I did
show to what extent man can acknowledge the reality of color, tone, etc.
without any clairvoyant perception. This has not yet been understood.
The scientific age is still too deeply entangled in Locke's manner of
thinking. I set it forth again, in philosophic terms, in 1911 at the
Philosophic Congress in Bologna. [57] And again it was
not understood. I tried to show how man's soul — spirit
organization does indeed indwell and permeate the physical and etheric
body during the waking state, but still remains inwardly independent. If
one senses this inward independence of the soul and spirit, then on also
has a feeling for what the soul and spirit have experienced during sleep
about the reality of green and yellow, G and C-sharp, warm and cold,
sour or sweet. But the scientific age was unwilling to go into a true
knowledge of man.
This description of the primary and secondary qualities shows quite
clearly how man got away from the correct feeling about himself and his
connection to the world. The same thing comes out in other connections.
Failing to grasp how the mathematical with its three-dimensional
character dwells in man, the thinkers likewise could not understand
man's spirituality. They would have had to see how man is in a position
to comprehend right-left by means of the symmetrical movements of his
arms and hands and other symmetrical movements. Through sensing the
course taken, for example, by his food, he can experience front-back. He
experiences up-down as he coordinates himself in this direction in his
earliest years. If we discern this, we see how man inwardly unfolds the
activity that produces the three dimensions of space. Let me point out
also that the animal does not have the vertical direction in the same
way as man does, since its main axis is horizontal, which is what man
can experience as front-back. The abstract space framework could no
longer produce anything other than mathematical, mechanistic, abstract
relationships in inorganic nature. It could not develop an inward
awareness of space in the animal or in man.
Thus no correct opinion could be reached in this scientific age
concerning the question: How does man relate to the animal, the animal
to man? What distinguishes them from one another? It was still dimly
felt that there was a difference between the two, hence one looked for
the distinguishing features. But nothing could be found in either man or
animal that was decisive and consistent. Here is a famous example: It
was asserted that man's upper jawbone, in which the upper teeth are
located, was in one piece, whereas in the animal, the front teeth were
located in a separate one, the inter-maxillary bone, with the actual
upper jawbone on either side of them. Man, it was thought, did not
possess this inter-maxillary bone. Since one could no longer find the
relationship of man to animal by inner soul-spirit means, one looked for
it in such external features and said that the animal had an
inter-maxillary bone and man did not.
Goethe could not put into words what I have said today concerning
primary and secondary qualities. But he had a healthy feeling about all
these matters. He knew instinctively that the difference between man and
animals must lie in the human form as a whole, not in any single
feature. This is why Goethe opposed the idea that the inter-maxillary
bone is missing in man. As a young man, he wrote an important article
suggesting that there is an inter-maxillary bone in man as well as in
the animal. He was able to prove this by showing that in the embryo the
inter-maxillary bone is still clearly evident in man although in early
childhood this bone fuses with the upper jaw, whereas it remains
separate in the animal. Goethe did all this out of a certain instinct,
and this instinct led him to say that one must not seek the difference
between man and animal in details of this kind; instead, it must be
sought for in the whole relation of man's form, soul, and spirit to the
world.
By opposing the naturalists who held that man lacks the
inter-maxillary bone Goethe brought man close to the animal. But he did
this in order to bring out the true difference as regards man's
essential nature. Goethe's approach out of instinctive knowledge put him
in opposition to the views of orthodox science, and this opposition has
remained to this day. This is why Goethe really found no successors in
the scientific world. On the contrary, as a consequence of all that had
developed since the Fifteenth Century in the scientific field, in the
Nineteenth Century the tendency grew stronger to approximate man to the
animal. The search for a difference in external details diminished with
the increasing effort to equate man as nearly as possible with the
animal. This tendency is reflected in what arose later on as the
Darwinian idea of evolution. This found followers, while Goethe's
conception did not. Some have treated Goethe as a kind of Darwinist,
because all they see in him is that, through his work on the
inter-maxillary bone,
[58] he brought man nearer to the animal. But
they fail to realize that he did this because he wanted to point out (he
himself did not say so in so many words, but it is implicit in his work)
that the difference between man and animal cannot be found in these
external details.
Since one no longer knew anything about man, one searched for man's
traits in the animal. The conclusion was that the animal traits are
simply a little more developed in man. As time went by, there was no
longer any inkling that even in regard to space man had a completely
different position. Basically, all views of evolution that originated
during the scientific age were formulated without any true knowledge of
man. One did not know what to make of man, so he was simply represented
as the culmination of the animal series. It was a though one said: Here
are the animals; they build up to a final degree of perfection, a
perfect animal; and this perfect animal is man.
My dear friends, I want to draw your attention to how matters have
proceeded with a certain inner consistency in the various branches of
scientific thinking since its first beginnings in the Fifteenth Century;
how we picture our relation to the world on the basis of physics, of
physiology, by saying: Out there is a silent and colorless world. It
affects us. We fashion the colors and sounds in ourselves as experiences
of the effects of the outer world.
At the same time we believe that the three dimensions of space exist
outside of us in the external world. We do this, because we have lost
the ability to comprehend man as a whole. We do this because our
theories of animal and man do not penetrate the true nature of man.
Therefore, in spite of its great achievements we can say that science
owes its greatness to the fact that it has completely missed the
essential nature of man. We were not really aware of the extent to which
science was missing this. A few especially enthusiastic materialistic
thinkers in the Nineteenth Century asserted that man cannot rightly lay
claim to anything like soul and spirit because what appears as soul and
spirit is only the effect of something taking place outside us in time
and space. Such enthusiasts describe how light works on us; how
something etheric (according to their theory) works into us through
vibrations along our nerves; how the external air also continues on in
breathing, etc. Summing it all up, they said that man is dependent on
every rise and fall of temperature, on any malformation of his nervous
system, etc. Their conclusion was that man is a creature pitifully
dependent on every draft or change of pressure.
Anyone who reads such descriptions with an open mind will notice
that, instead of dealing with the true nature of man, they are
describing something that turns man into a nervous wreck. The right
reply to such descriptions is that a man so dependent on every little
draft of air is not a normal person but a neurasthenic. But they spoke
of this neurasthenic as if he were typical. They left out his real
nature, recognizing only what might make him into a neurasthenic.
Through the peculiar character of this kind of thinking about nature,
all understanding was gradually lost. This is what Goethe revolted
against, though he was unable to express his insights in clearly
formulated sentences.
Matters such as these must be seen as part of the great change in
scientific thinking since the Fifteenth Century. Then they will throw
light on what is essential in this development. I would like to put it
like this: Goethe in his youth took a keen interest in what science had
produced in its various domains. He studied it, he let it stimulate him,
but he never agreed with everything that confronted him, because in all
of it he sensed that man was left out of consideration. He had an
intense feeling for man as a whole. This is why he revolted in a variety
of areas against the scientific views that he saw around him. It is
important to see this scientific development since the Fifteenth Century
against the background of Goethe's world conception. Proceeding from a
strictly historical standpoint, one can clearly perceive how the real
being of man is missing in the scientific approach, missing in the
physical sciences as well as in the biological.
This is a description of the scientific view, not a criticism. Let
us assume that somebody says: "Here I have water. I cannot use it
in this state. I separate the oxygen from hydrogen, because I need the
hydrogen." He then proceeds to do so. If I then say what he has
done, this is not criticism of his conduct. I have no business to tell
him he is doing something wrong and should leave the water alone. Nor is
it criticism, when I saw that since the Fifteenth Century science has
taken the world of living beings and separated from it the true nature
of man, discarding it and retaining what this age required. It then led
this dehumanized science to the triumphs that have been achieved.
It is not a criticism if something like this is said; it is only a
description. The scientist of modern times needed a dehumanized nature,
just as chemist needs deoxygenized hydrogen and therefore has to split
water into its two components. The point is to understand that we must
not constantly fall into the error of looking to science for an
understanding of man.
∴
Lecture VII
2 January 1923, Dornach
Continuing with yesterday's considerations concerning the inability
of the scientific world conception to grasp the nature of man, we can
say that in all domains of science something is missing that is also
absent in the mathematical-mechanistic sphere. This sphere has been
divorced from man, as if man were absent from the mathematical
experience. This line of thought results in a tendency to also separate
other processes in the world from man. This in its turn produces an
inability to create a real bridge between man and world.
I shall discuss another consequence of this inability later on. Let
us focus first of all on the basic reason why science has developed in
this way. It was because we lost the power to experience inwardly
something that is spoken of in Anthroposophy today and that in former
times was perceived by a sort of instinctive clairvoyance. Scientific
perception has lost the ability to see into man and grasp how he is
composed of different elements.
Let us recall the anthroposophical idea that man is composed of four
members — the physical body, the etheric body, the astral body and
the I-organization. I need not go into detail about this formation,
since you can find it all in my book Theosophy.
[59] When we observe the physical body and consider
the possibility of inward experiencing one's physical body — we
should begin by asking: What do we experience in regard to it? We
experience what I have frequently spoken about recently; namely, the
right-left, up-down, and front-back directions. We experience motion,
the change of place of one's own body. To some extent at least, we also
experience weight in various degrees. But weight is experienced in a
highly modified form. When these things were still experienced within
our various members, we reflected on them a good deal; but in the
scientific age, no one gives them any thought. Facts that are of
monumental importance for a world comprehension are completely ignored.
Take the following fact. Assume that you have to carry a person who
weighs as much as you do. Imagine that you carry this person a certain
distance. You will consciously experience his weight. Of course, as you
walk this distance, you are carrying yourself as well. But you do not
experience this in the same way. You carry your own weight through
space, but you do not experience this. Awareness of one's own weight is
something quite different. In old age, we are apt to say that we feel
the weight of our limbs. To some extent this is connected with weight,
because old age entails a certain disintegration of the organism. This
in turn tears the individual members out of the inward experience and
makes them independent — atomizes them, as it were — and in
atomization they fall a prey to gravity. But we do not actually feel
this at any given moment of our life, so this statement that we feel the
weight of our limbs is really only a figure of speech. A more exact
science might show that it is not purely figurative, but be that as it
may, the experience of our weight does not impinge strongly on our
consciousness.
This shows that we have an inherent need to obliterate certain
effects that are unquestionably working within us. We obliterate them by
means of opposite effects ("opposite" in the sense brought
out by the analogy between man and the course of the year in my recent
morning lectures).
[60] Nevertheless, whether we are
dealing with processes that can be experienced relatively clearly, such
as the three dimensions or motion, or with less obvious ones such as
those connected with weight, they are all processes that can be
experienced in the physical body.
What was thus experienced in former times has since been completely
divorced from man. This is most evident in the case of mathematics. The
reason it is less obvious in other experiences of the physical body is
that the corresponding processes in the body, such as weight or gravity,
are completely extinguished for today's form of consciousness. These
processes, however, were not always completely obliterated. Under the
influence of the mood prevailing under the scientific world conception,
people today no longer have any idea of how different man's inner
awareness was in the past. True, he did not consciously carry his weight
through space in former times. Instead, he had the feeling that along
with this weight, there was a counterweight. When he learned something,
as was the case with the neophytes in the mysteries, he learned to
perceive how, while he always carried his own weight in and with
himself, the counter-effect is constantly active in light. It can really
be said that man felt that he had to thank the spiritual element
indwelling the light for counteracting, within him, the soul-spirit
element activity in gravity. In short, we can show in many ways that in
older times there was no feeling that anything was completely divorced
from man. Within himself, man experienced the processes and events as
they occurred in nature. When he observed the fall of a stone, for
example, in external nature (an event physically separated from him) he
experienced the essence of movement. He experienced this by comparing it
with what such a movement would be like in himself. When he saw a
falling stone, he experienced something like this: "If I wanted to
move in the same way, I would have to acquire a certain speed, and in a
falling stone the speed differs from what I observe, for instance, in a
slowly crawling creature." He experienced the speed of the falling
stone by applying his experience of movement to the observation of the
falling stone. The processes of the external world that we study in
physics today were in fact also viewed objectively by the man of former
times, but he gained his knowledge with the aid of his own experiences
in order to rediscover in the external world the processes going on
within himself.
Until the beginning of the Fifteenth Century, all the conceptions of
physics were pervaded by something of which one can say that it brought
even the physical activities of objects close to the inner life of man.
Man experienced them in unison with nature. But with the onset of the
Fifteenth Century begins the divorce of the observation of such
processes from man. Along with it came the severance of mathematics, a
way of thinking which from then on was combined with all science. The
inner experience in the physical body was totally lost. What can be
termed the inner physics of man was lost. External physics was divorced
from man, along with mathematics. The progress thereby achieved
consisted in the objectifying of the physical. What is physical can be
looked at in two ways. Staying with the example of the falling stone, it
can be traced with external vision.
It can also be brought together with the experience of the speed that
would have to be achieved if one wanted to run as fast as the stone
falls. This produces comprehension that goes through the whole man, not
one related only to visual perception.
To see what happened to the older world view at the dawn of the
Fifteenth Century, let us look at a man in whom the transition can be
observed particularly well; namely, Galileo.
[61] Galileo is
in a sense the discoverer of the laws governing falling objects.
Galileo's main aim was to determine the distance traveled in the first
second by a falling body. The older world view placed the visual
observation of the falling stone side by side with the inward experience
of the speed needed to run at an equal pace. The inner experience was
placed alongside that of the falling stone. Galileo also observed the
falling stone, but he did not compare it with the inward experience.
Instead, he measured the distance traveled by the stone in the first
second of its fall. Since the stone falls with increasing speed, Galileo
also measured the following segments of its path. He did not align this
with any inward experience, but with an externally measured process that
had nothing to do with man, a process that was completely divorced from
man. Thus, in perception and knowledge, the physical was so completely
removed from man that he was not aware that he had the physical inside
him as well.
At that time, around the beginning of the Seventeenth Century, a
number of thinkers who wanted to be progressive began to revolt against
Aristotle, [62] who throughout the
Middle Ages had been considered the preeminent authority on science. If
Aristotle's explanations of the falling stone (misunderstood in most
cases today) are looked at soberly, we notice that when something is
beheld in the world outside, he always points out how it would be if man
himself were to undergo the same process. For him, it is not a matter of
determining a given speed by measuring it, but to think of speed in such
a way that it can be related to some human experience. Naturally, if you
say you must achieve a particular speed, you feel that something alive,
something filled with vigor, will be needed for you to do this. You feel
a certain inner impetus, and the last thing you would assume is that
something is pulling you in the direction you were heading. You would
think that you were pushing, not that you were being pulled. This is why
the force of attraction, gravity, begins to mean something only in the
Seventeenth Century.
Man's idea about nature began to change radically; not just the law
of falling bodies, but all the ideas of physics. Another example is the
law of inertia, it is generally called. The very name reveals its origin
within man. (There is a play on words here. The German term for inertia,
Trägheit, really means laziness.) Inertia is something that
can be inwardly felt but what has become of the law of inertia in
physics under the influence of "Galileoism?" the physicist
says: A body, or rather a point, on which no external influence is
exercises, which is left to itself, moves through space with uniform
velocity. This means that throughout all time-spans it travels the same
distance in each second. If no external influence interferes, and the
body has achieved a given speed per second, it travels the same distance
in each succeeding second.
It is inert. Lacking an external influence, it continues on and on
without change. All the physicist does is measure the distance per
second, and a body is called inert if the velocity remains constant.
There was a time when one felt differently about this and asked: How
is a moving body, traveling a constant distance per second, experienced?
It could be experienced by remaining on one and the same condition
without ever changing one's behavior. At most, this could only be an
ideal for man. He can attain this ideal of inertia only to a very small
degree. But if you look at what is called inertia in ordinary life, you
see that it is pretty much like doing the same thing every second of
your life.
From the Fifteenth Century on, the whole orientation of the human
mind was led to such a point that we can fairly say that man forgot his
own inward experience. This happens first with the inner experience of
the physical organism — man forgets it. What Galileo thought out
and applied to matters close to man, such as the law of inertia, was not
applied in a wide context. And it was indeed merely thought out, even if
Galileo was dealing with things that can be observed in nature.
We know how, by placing the sun in the center instead of the earth,
and by letting the planets move in circles around the sun, and by
calculating the position of a given planetary body in the heavens,
Copernicus produced a new cosmic system in a physical sense. This was
the picture that Copernicus drew of our planetary, our solar system. And
it was a picture that certainly can be drawn. Yet, this picture did not
make a radical turn toward the mathematical attitude that completely
divorces the external world from man. Anyone reading Copernicus's text
gets the impression that Copernicus still felt the following. In the
complicated lines, by means of which the earlier astronomy tried to
grasp the solar system, it not only summed up the optical locations of
the planets; it also had a feeling for what would be experienced if one
stood amid these movements of the planets. In former ages people had a
very clear idea of the epicycles the planets were thought to describe.
In all this there was still a certain amount of human feeling. Just as
you can understand the position of, let us say, an arm when you are
painting a picture of a person because you can feel what it is like to
be in such a position, so there was something alive in tracing the
movement described by a planet around its fixed star. Indeed, even in
Kepler's [63] case — perhaps especially in his case
— there is still something of a human element in his calculating
the orbits described by the planets.
Now Newton applies Galileo's abstracted principle to the heavenly
bodies, adopting something like the Copernican view and conceiving
things somewhat as follows: A central body, let us say a sun, attracts a
planet in such a way that this force of attraction decreases in
proportion to the square of the distance. It becomes smaller and smaller
in proportion to the square, but increases in proportion to the mass of
the bodies. If the attracting body has a greater mass, the force of
attraction is porportionately greater.
If the distance is greater, the force of attraction decreases, but
always in such a way that if the distance is twice as great, the
attraction is four times less; if it is three times as great, nine times
less, and so forth. Pure measuring is instilled into the picture, which,
again, is conceived as completely abstracted from man. This was not yet
so with Copernicus and Kepler but with Newton, a so-called
"objective" something is excogitated and there is no longer
any experience, it is all mere excogitation. Lines are drawn in the
direction in which one looks and forces are, as it were, imagined into
them, since what one sees is not force; the force has to be dreamed up.
Naturally, one says "thought up" as long as one believes in
the whole business; but when one no longer has faith in it, one says,
"dreamed up."
Thus we can say that through Newton the whole abstracted physical
mode of conception becomes generalized so far that is applied to the
whole universe. In short, the aim is to completely forget all experience
within man's physical body; to objectify what was formerly pictured as
closely related to the experience of the physical body; to view it in
outer space independent of the physical corporeality, although this
space had first been torn out of the body experience; and to find ways
to speak of space without even thinking about the human being. Through
separation from the physical body, through separation of nature's
phenomena from man's experience in the physical body, modern physics
arises. It comes into existence along with this separation of certain
processes of nature from self-experience within the physical human body
(yellow in sketch). Self experience is forgotten (red in Fig. 1)
By permeating all external phenomena with abstract mathematics, this
kind of physics could not longer understand man. What had been separated
from man could not be reconnected. In short, there emerges a total
inability to bring science back to man.
In physical respects you do not notice this quite so much; but you
do notice it if you ask: What about man's self-experience in the etheric
body, in this subtle organism? Man experiences quite a bit in it. But
this was separated from man even earlier and more radically. This
abstraction, however, was not as successful as in physics. Let us go
back to a scientist of the first Christian centuries, the physician
Galen. [64]
Looking at what lived in external nature and following the traditions of
his time, Galen distinguished four elements — earth, water, air
and fire (we would say warmth.) We see these if we look at nature. But,
looking inward and focusing on the self-experience of the etheric body,
[65]
one asks: How do I experience
these elements, the solid, the watery, the airy and the fiery in myself?
Then, in those times the answer was: I experience them with my etheric
body. One experienced it as inwardly felt movements of the fluids; the
earth as "black gall," the watery as "phlegm,"
the airy as "pneuma" (what is taken in through the breathing
process,) and warmth as "blood." In the fluids, in what
circulates in the human organism, the same thing was experienced as what
was observed externally. Just as the movement of the falling stone was
accompanied by an experience in the physical body, so the elements were
experienced in inward processes. The metabolic process, where (so it was
thought) gall, phlegm, and blood work into each other, was felt as the
inner experience of one's own body, but a form of inward experience to
which corresponded the external processes occurring between air, water,
fire and earth.
Warmth
-Blood
-Ego
Organization
Air
-Pneuma
-Astral Body
Water
-Phlegm
-Etheric Body
-Chemistry
Earth
-Black Gall
-Physical body
-Physics
Here, however, we did not succeed in completely forgetting all inner
life and still satisfying external observation. In the case of a falling
body, one could measure something; for example, the distance traveled in
the first second. One arrived at a "law of inertia" by
thinking of moving points that do not alter their condition of movement
but maintain their speed. By attempting to eject from the inward
experience something that the ancients strongly felt to be a specific
inner experience; namely, the four elements, one was able to forget the
inner content but one could not find in the external world any measuring
system. Therefore the attempt to objectify what related to these
matters, as was done in physics, remained basically unsuccessful to this
day. Chemistry could have become a science that would rank alongside
physics, if it had been possible to take as much of the etheric body
into the external world as was accomplished in the physical body. In
chemistry, however, unlike physics, we speak to this day of something
rather undefined and vague, when referring to its laws.
[66] What was done with
physics in regard to the physical body was in fact the aim of chemistry
in regard to the etheric body. Chemistry states that if substances
combine chemically, and in doing so can completely alter their
properties, something is naturally happening.
But if one wants to go beyond this conception, which is certainly
the simplest and most convenient, one really does not know much about
this process. Water consists of hydrogen and oxygen; the two must be
conceived as mixed together in the water somehow but no inwardly
experiencable concept can be formed of this. It is commonly explained in
a very external way: hydrogen consists of atoms (or molecules if you
will) and so does oxygen. These intermingle, collide, and cling to one
another, and so forth. This means that, although the inner experience
was forgotten, one did not find oneself in the same position as in
physics, where one could measure (and increasingly physics became a
matter of measuring, counting and weighing.) Instead, one could only
hypothesize the inner process. In a certain respect, it has remained
this way in chemistry to this day, because what is pictured as the inner
nature of chemical processes is basically only something read into them
by thought.
Chemistry will attain the level of physics only when with full
insight into these matters, we can again relate chemistry with man,
though not, of course, with the direct experience possessed by the old
instinctive clairvoyance. We will only succeed in this when we gain
enough insight into physics to be able to consolidate our isolated
fragments of knowledge into a world conception and bring our thoughts
concerning the individual phenomena into connection with man. What
happens on one side, when we forget all inner experience and concentrate
on measuring externals (thus remaining stuck in the so-called
"objective") takes its revenge on the other side. It is easy
enough to say that inertia is expressed by the movement of a point that
travels the same distance in each succeeding second. But there is no
such point. This uniform movement occurs nowhere in the domain of human
observation. A moving object is always part of some relationship, and
its velocity is hampered here or there. In short, what could be
described as inert mass,
[67] or could
be reduced to the law of inertia, does not exist. If we speak of
movement and cannot return to the living inner accompanying experience
of it, if we cannot relate the velocity of a falling body to the way we
ourselves would experience this movement, then we must indeed say that
we are entirely outside the movement and must orient ourselves by the
external world. If I observe a moving body (see Fig. 7) and if these are
its successive positions, I must somehow perceive that this body moves.
If behind it there is a stationary wall, I follow the direction of
movements and tell myself that the body moves on in that direction. But
what is necessary in addition is that from my own position (dark circle)
I guide this observation, in other words, become aware of an inward
experience. If I completely leave out the human being and orient myself
only out there, then, regardless of whether the object moves or remains
stationary, while the wall moves, the result will be the same. I shall
no longer be able to distinguish whether the body moves in one or the
wall behind it in the opposite direction. I can basically make all the
calculations under either one or the other assumption.
I lose the ability to understand a movement inwardly if I do not
partake of it with my own experience. This applies, if I may say so, to
many other aspects of physics. Having excluded the participating
experience, I am prevented from building any kind of bridge to the
objective process. If I myself am running, I certainly cannot claim that
it is a matter of indifference whether I run or the ground beneath me
moves in the opposite direction. But if I am watching another person
moving over a given area, it makes no difference for merely external
observation whether he is running or the ground beneath him is moving in
the opposite direction. Our present age has actually reached the point,
where we experience, if I may put it this way, the world spirit's
revenge for our making everything physical abstract.
Newton was still quite certain that he could assume absolute
movements, but now we can see numerous scientists trying to establish
the fact that movement, the knowledge of movement, has been lost along
with the inner experience of it. Such is the essence of the Theory of
Relativity, [68] which is trying to pull the ground from under
Newtonism. This theory of relativity is a natural historical result. It
cannot help but exist today. We will not progress beyond it if we remain
with those ideas that have been completely separated from the human
element. If we want to understand rest or motion, we must partake in the
experience. If we do not do this, then even rest and motion are only
relative to one another.
∴
Lecture VIII
3 January 1923, Dornach
I have tried to show how various domains of scientific thought
originated in modern times. Now I will try to throw light from a certain
standpoint on what was actually happening in the development of these
scientific concepts. Then we shall better understand what these concepts
signify in the whole evolutionary process of mankind. We must clearly
understand that the phenomena of external culture are inwardly permeated
by a kind of pulse beat that originates from deeper insights. Such
insights need not always be ones that are commonly taught, but still
they are at the bottom of the development. Now, I would only like to say
that we can better understand what we are dealing with in this direction
if we include in our considerations what in certain epochs was practiced
as initiation science, a science of the deeper foundations of life and
history.
We know that the farther we go back in history,
[69] the more we discover an instinctive spiritual
knowledge, an instinctive clairvoyant perception of what goes on behind
the scenes. Moreover, we know that it is possible in our time to attain
to a deeper knowledge, because since the last third of the Nineteenth
Century, after the high tide of materialistic concepts and feelings,
simply through the relationship of the spiritual world to the physical,
the possibility arose to draw spiritual knowledge once again directly
from the super-sensible world. Since the last third of the Nineteenth
Century, it has been possible to deepen human knowledge to the point
where it can behold the foundations of what takes place in the external
processes of nature.
So we can say that an ancient instinctive initiation science made
way for an exoteric civilization in which little was felt of any direct
spirit knowledge, but now it is fully conscious rather than
instinctive.
We stand at the beginning of this development of a new spirit
knowledge. It will unfold further in the future. If we have a certain
insight into what man regarded as knowledge during the age of the old
instinctive science of initiation, we can discover that until the
beginning of the Fourteenth Century, opinions prevailed in the civilized
world that cannot be directly compared with any of our modern
conceptions about nature. They were ideas of quite a different kind.
Still less can they be compared with what today's science calls
psychology. There too, we would have to say that it is of quite a
different kind. The soul and spirit of man as well as the physical realm
of nature were grasped in concepts and ideas that today are understood
only by men who specifically study initiation science. The whole manner
of thinking and feeling was quite different in former times.
If we examine the ancient initiation science, we find that, in spite
of the fragmentary ways in which it has been handed down, it had
profound insights, deep conceptions, concerning man and his relation to
the world.
People today do not greatly esteem a work like De Divisione
Naturae (Concerning the Division of Nature) by John Scotus Erigena
[70]
in the Ninth Century. They do not bother
with it because such a work is not regarded as an historical document
since it comes from a time when men thought differently from the way
they think today, so differently that we can no longer understand such a
book. When ordinary philosophers describe such topics in their
historical writings, one is offered mere empty words. Scholars no longer
enter into the fundamental spirit of a work such as that of John Scotus
Erigena on the division of nature, where even the term nature signifies
something other than in modern science. If, with the insight of
spiritual science, we do enter into the spirit of such a text, we must
come to the following rather odd conclusion: This Scotus Erigena
developed ideas that give the impression of extraordinary penetration
into the essence of the world, but he presented these ideas in an
inadequate and ineffective form. At the risk of speaking disrespectfully
of a work that is after all very valuable, one has to say that Erigena
himself no longer fully understood what he was writing about. One can
see that in his description. Even for him, though not to the same extent
as with modern historians of philosophy, the words that he had gleaned
from tradition were more or less words only, and he could no longer
enter into their deeper meaning. Reading his works, we find ourselves
increasingly obliged to go farther back in history. Erigena's writings
lead us directly back to those of the so-called pseudo-Dionysius the
Areopagite.
[71] I will now leave aside the historical problem of when
Dionysius lived, and so forth. But again from Dionysius the Areopagite
one is led still farther back. To continue the search one must be
equipped with spiritual science. But finally, going back to the second
and third millennia before Christ, one comes upon very deep insights
that have been lost to mankind. Only as a faint echo are they present in
writings such as those of Erigena.
Even if we go no further back than the Scholastics, we can find,
hidden under their pedantic style, profound ideas concerning the way in
which man apprehends the outer world, and how there lives the
super-sensible on one side and on the other side the sense perceptible,
and so on. If we take the stream of tradition founded on Aristotle who,
in his logical but pedantic way, had in turn gathered together the
ancient knowledge that had been handed down to him, we find the same
thing — deep insights that were well understood in ancient times
and survived feebly into the Middle Ages, being repeated in the
successive epochs, and were always less and less understood. That is the
characteristic process. At last in the Thirteenth or Fourteenth Century,
the understanding disappears almost entirely, and a new spirit emerges,
the spirit of Copernicus and Galileo, which I have described in the
previous lectures.
In all studies, such as those I have just outlines, it is found that
this ancient knowledge is handed down through the ages until the
Fourteenth Century, though less and less understood. This ancient
knowledge amounted essentially to an inner experience of what goes on in
man himself. The explanations of the last few lectures should make this
comprehensible: It is the experiencing of the mathematical-mechanical
element in human movement, the experiencing of a certain chemical
principle, as we would say today, in the circulation of man's bodily
fluids, which are permeated by the etheric body. Hence, we can even look
at the table that I put on the blackboard yesterday from an historical
standpoint. If we look at the being of man with our initiation science
today, we have the physical body, the etheric body, the astral body (the
inner life of the soul,) and the ego organization. As I pointed out
yesterday, there existed (arising out of the ancient initiation science)
an inner experience of the physical body, an inward experience of
movement, an inner experience of the dimensionality of space, as well as
experiences of other physical and mechanical processes. We can call this
inner experience the experiencing of physics in man. But this experience
of physics in man is at the same time the cognition of the very laws of
physics and mechanics. There was a physics of man directed toward the
physical body. It would not have occurred to anyone in those times to
search for physics other than through the experience in man. Now, in the
age of Galileo and Copernicus, together with the mathematics that was
thenceforth applied in physics, what was inwardly experienced is cast
out of man and grasped abstractly. It can be said that physics sunders
itself from man, whereas formerly it was contained in man himself.
Something similar was experienced with the fluid processes, the
bodily fluids of the human organism. These too were inwardly
experienced. Yesterday I referred to the Galen who, in the first
Christian centuries, described the following fluids in man: black gall,
blood, phlegm, and the ordinary means of the intermingling of these
fluids by the way they influence each other. Galen did not arrive at
these statements by anything resembling today's physiological methods.
They were based mainly on inward experiences. For Galen too these were
largely a tradition, but what he thus took from tradition we once
experienced inwardly in the fluid part of the human organism, which in
turn was permeated by the etheric body.
For this reason, in the beginning of my Riddles of
Philosophy, [72] I did not describe
the Greek philosophers in the customary way. Read any ordinary history
of philosophy and you will find this subject presented more or less as
follows: Thales [73] pondered on the origin of our sense world and sought
for it in water. Heraclitus looked for it in fire. Others looked for it
in air. Still others in solid matter, for example in something like
atoms. It is amazing that this can be recounted without questions being
raised. People today do not notice that it basically defies explanation
why Thales happened to designate water while Heraclitus
[74] chose fire as the source of all
things. Read my book Riddles of Philosophy, and you will see that
the viewpoint of Thales, expressed in the sentence "All things
have originated from water," is based on an inner experience. He
inwardly felt the activity of what in his day was termed the watery
element. He sensed that the basis of the external process in nature was
related to this inner activity; thus he described the external out of
inner experiences. It was the same with Heraclitus who, as we would say
today, was of a different temperament. Thales, as a phlegmatic, was
sensitive to the inward "water" or "phlegm."
Therefore he described the world from the phlegmatic's viewpoint:
everything has come from water. Heraclitus, as a choleric, experienced
the inner "fire." He described the world the way he
experienced it. Besides them, there were other thinkers, who are no
longer mentioned by external tradition, who knew still more concerning
these matters. Their knowledge was handed down and still existed as
tradition in the first Christian centuries; hence Galen could speak of
the four components of man's inner fluidic system.
What was then known concerning the inner fluids, namely, how these
four fluids — yellow gall, black gall, blood, and phlegm —
influence and mix with one another really amounts to an inner human
chemistry, though it is of course considered childish today. No other
form of chemistry existed in those days. The external phenomena that
today belong to the field of chemistry were then evaluated according to
these inward experiences. We can therefore speak of an inner chemistry
based on experiences of the fluid man who is permeated by the ether
body. Chemistry was tied to man in former ages. Later it emerged, as did
mathematics and physics, and became external chemistry (see Figure 1.)
Try to imagine how the physics and chemistry of ancient times were felt
by men. They were experienced as something that was, as it were, a part
of themselves, not as something that is mere description of an external
nature and its processes. The main point was: it was experienced
physics, experienced chemistry.
In those ages when men felt
external nature in their physical and etheric bodies, the contents of
the astral body and the ego organization were also experienced
differently than in later times.
Today was have a psychology, but it is only an inventory of
abstractions, though no one admits this. You will find in it thinking,
feeling, willing, as well as memory, imagination, and so forth, but
treated as mere abstractions. This gradually arose from what was still
considered as one's own soul contents. One had cast out chemistry and
physics; thinking, feeling and willing were retained. But what was left
eventually became so diluted that it turned into no more than an
inventory of lifeless empty abstractions, and it can be readily proved
that this is so. Take, for example, the people who still spoke of
thinking or willing as late as the Fifteenth or Sixteenth Century.
[75] If you study the older texts on these subjects you
will see that people expressed themselves concerning these matters in a
concrete way. You have the feeling, when such a person speaks about
thinking, that he speaks as if this thinking were actually a series of
inner processes within him, as if the thoughts were colliding with each
other or supporting each other. This is still an experiencing of
thoughts. It is not yet as abstract a matter as it became later on.
During and towards the end of the Nineteenth Century, it was an easy
thing for the philosophers to deny all reality to these abstractions.
They saw thoughts as inner mirror pictures, as was done in an especially
brilliant way by Richard Wahle, who declared that the ego, thinking,
feeling, and willing were only illusions. Instead of abstractions, the
inner soul contents become illusions.
In the age when man felt that his walking was a process that took
place simultaneously in him and the world, and when he still sensed the
circulating fluids within him, he knew, for instance, that when he moved
about in the heat of the sun (when external influences were present)
that the blood and phlegm circulated differently in him than was the
case in winter. Such a man experienced the blood and phlegm circulation
within himself, but he experienced it together with the sunshine or the
lack thereof. And just as he experienced physical and chemical aspects
in union with the outside world, so he also experienced thinking,
feeling, and willing together with the world. He did not think they were
occurring only within himself as was done in later ages when they
gradually evaporated into complete abstractions. Instead he experienced
what occurred in him in thinking, feeling, and willing, or in the
circulation of the fluids as part of the realm of the astral, the soul
being of man, which in that age was the subject of a psychology.
Psychology now became tightly tied to man. With the dawn of the
scientific age, man drove physics and chemistry out into the external
world; psychology, on the other hand, he drove into himself. This
process can be traced in Francis Bacon and John Locke. All that is
experienced of the external world, such as tone, color, and warmth, is
pressed into man's interior.
This process is even more pronounced in regard to the ego
organization. This gradually became a very meager experience. The way
man looked into himself, the ego became by degrees something like a mere
point. For that reason it became easy to philosophers to dispute its
very existence. Not ego consciousness, but the experience of the ego was
for men of former ages something rich in content and fully real. This
ego experience expressed itself in something that was a loftier science
than psychology, a science that can be called pneumatology. In later
times this was also pressed into the interior and thinned out into our
present quite diluted ego feeling.
When man had the inward experience of his physical body, he had the
experience of physics; simultaneously, he experienced what corresponds
in outer nature to the processes in his physical body. It is similar in
the case of the etheric body. Not only the etheric, was experienced
inwardly, but also the physical fluid system, which is controlled by the
etheric. Now, what is inwardly experienced when man perceives the
psychological, the processes of his astral body? The "air
man" — if I may put it this way — is inwardly
experienced. We are not only solid organic formations, not only fluids
or water formations, we are always gaseous-airy as well. We breathe in
the air and breathe it out again. We experienced the substance of
psychology in intimate union with the inner assimilation of air. This is
why psychology was more concrete. When the living experience of air
(which can also be outwardly traced) was cast out of the thought
contents, these thought contents became increasingly abstract, became
mere thought. Just think how an old Indian philosopher strove in his
exercises to become conscious of the fact that in the breathing process
something akin to the thought process was taking place. He regulated his
breathing process in order to progress his thinking. He knew that
thinking, feeling and willing are not as flimsy as we today make them
out to be. He knew that through breathing they were related to both
outer and inner nature, hence with air. As we can say that man expelled
the physical and chemical aspects from his organization, we can also say
that he sucked in the psychological aspect, but in doing so he rejected
the external element, the air-breath experience. He withdrew his own
being from the physical and chemical elements and merely observed the
outer world with physics and chemistry; whereas he squeezed external
nature (air) out of the psychological. Likewise, he squeezed the warmth
element out of the pneumatological realm, thus reducing it to the rarity
of the ego.
If I call the physical and etheric bodies, the "lower
man," and call the astral body and ego-organization the
"upper man," I can say that in the transition from an older
epoch to the scientific age, man lost the inner physical and chemical
experience, and came to grasp external nature only with his concepts of
physics and chemistry. In psychology and pneumatology, on the other
hand, man developed conceptions from which he eliminated outer nature
and came to experience only so much of nature as remained in his
concepts. In psychology, this was enough so that he at least still had
words for what went on in his soul. As to the ego, however, this was so
little that pneumatology (partially because theological dogmatism had
prepared this development) completely faded out. It shrank down to the
mere dot of the ego.
All this took the place of what had been experienced as a unity,
when men of old said: We have four elements, earth, water, air and fire.
Earth we experience in ourselves when we experience the physical body.
Water we experience in ourselves when we experience the etheric body as
the agent that moves, mixes, and separates the fluids. Air is
experienced when the astral body is experienced in thinking, feeling,
and willing, because these three are experienced as surging with the
inner breathing process. Finally, warmth, or fire as it was then called,
was experienced in the sensation of the ego.
So we may say that the modern scientific view developed by way of a
transformation of man's whole relation to himself. If you follow
historical evolution with these insights, you will find what I told you
earlier — that in each new epoch we see new descriptions of the
old traditions, but these are always less and less understood. The
worlds of men like Paracelsus, van Helmont, or Jacob Boehme,
[76] bear witness to such ancient
traditions.
One who has insight into these matters gets the impression that in
Jacob Boehme's case a very simple man is speaking out of sources that
would lead too far today to discuss. He is difficult to comprehend
because of his clumsiness. But Jacob Boehme shows profound insight in
his awkward descriptions, insights that have been handed down through
the generations. What was the situation of a person like Jacob Boehme?
Giordano Bruno, his contemporary, stood among the most advanced men of
his time, whereas we see in Jacob Boehme's case that he obviously read
all kinds of books that are naturally forgotten today. These were full
of rubbish. But Boehme was able to find a meaning in them. Awkwardly and
with great difficulty Boehme presents the primeval wisdom that he had
gleaned from his still more awkward and inadequate sources. His inward
enlightenment enabled him to return to an earlier stage.
If we now look at the Fifteenth, Sixteenth, and especially the
Seventeenth and Eighteenth centuries, and if we leave aside isolated
people like Paracelsus and Boehme (who appear like monuments to a bygone
age,) and if we look at the exoteric stream of human development in the
light of initiation science, we gain the impression that nobody knows
anything at all anymore about the deeper foundations of things. Physics
and chemistry have been eliminated from man, and alchemy has become the
subject of derision. Of course, people were justified in scoffing at it,
because what still remained of the ancient traditions in medieval
alchemy could well be made fun of. All that is left is psychology, which
has become confined to man's inner being, and a very meager
pneumatology. People have broken with everything that was formerly known
of human nature., On one hand, they experience what has been separated
from man; and on the other, what has been chaotically relegated into his
interior. And in all our search for knowledge, we see what I have just
described.
In the Seventeenth Century, a theory arose that remains quite
unintelligible if considered by itself, although if it is viewed in the
context of history it becomes comprehensible. The theory was that those
processes in the human body that have to do with the intake of food, are
based on a kind of fermentation. The foods man eats are permeated with
saliva and then with digestive fluids such as those in the pancreas, and
thus various degrees of fermentation processes, as they were called, are
achieved. If one looks at these ideas from today's viewpoint (which
naturally will also be outgrown in the future) one can only make fun of
them. But if we enter into these ideas and examine them closely, we
discover the source of these apparently foolish ideas. The ancient
traditions, which in a man like Galen were based on inward experiences
and were thus well justified, were now on the verge of extinction. At
the same time, what was to become external objective chemistry was only
in its beginnings. Men had lost the inner knowledge, and the external
had not yet developed. Therefore, they found themselves able to speak
about digestion only in quite feeble neo-chemical terms, such as the
vague idea of fermentation. Such men were the late followers of Galen's
teachings. They still felt that in order to comprehend man, one must
start from the movements of man's fluids, his fluid nature. But at the
same time, they were beginning to view chemical aspects only by means of
the external processes. Therefore they seized the idea of fermentation,
which could be observed externally, and applied it to man. Man had
become an empty bag because he no longer experienced anything within
himself. What had grown to be external science was poured into this bag.
In the Seventeenth Century, of course, there was not much science to
pour. People had the vague idea about fermentation and similar
processes, and these were rashly applied to man. Thus arose the
so-called iatrochemical school
[77] of medicine.
In considering these iatrochemists, we must realize that they still
had some inkling of the ancient doctrine of fluids, which was based on
inner experience. Others, who were more or less contemporaries of the
iatrochemists, no longer had any such inkling, so they began to view man
the way he appears to us today when we open an anatomy book. In such
books we find descriptions of the bones, the stomach, the liver, etc.
and we are apt to get the impression that this is all there is to know
about man and that he consists of more or less solid organs with sharply
defined contours. Of course, from a certain aspect, they do exist. But
the solid aspect — the earth element, to use the ancient
terminology — comprises at most one tenth of man's organization.
It is more accurate to say that man is a column of fluids. The mistake
is not in what is actually said, but in the whole method of
presentation. It is gradually forgotten that man is a column of fluids
in which the clearly contoured organs swim. Laymen see the pictures and
have the impression that this is all they need to understand the body.
But this is misleading. It is only one tenth of man. The remainder ought
to be described by drawing a continuous stream of fluids (see Figure 2)
interacting in the most manifold ways in the stomach, liver and so
forth. Quite erroneous conceptions arise as to how man's organism
actually functions, because only the sharply outlined organs are
observed. This is why in the Nineteenth Century, people were astonished
to see that if one drinks a glass of water, it appears to completely
penetrate the body and be assimilated by his organs. But when a second
or third glass of water is consumed, it no longer gives the impression
that it is digested in the same manner. These matters were noticed but
could no longer be explained, because a completely false view was held
concerning the fluid organization of man. Here etheric body is the
driving agent that mixes or separates the fluids, and brings about the
processes of organic chemistry in man.
In the Seventeenth Century, people really began to totally ignore
this "fluid man" and to focus only on the solidly contoured
parts. In this realm of clearly outlined parts, everything takes place
in a mechanical way. One part pushes another; the other moves; things
get pumped; it all works like suction or pressure pumps. The body is
viewed from a mechanical standpoint, as existing only through the
interplay of solidly contoured organs. Out of the iatrochemical theory
or alongside it, there arose iatromechanics and even iatromathematics.
[78]
Naturally, people began to think that the heart is really a pump
that mechanically pumps the blood through the body, because they no
longer knew that our inner fluids have their own life and therefore move
on their own. They never dreamed that the heart is only a sense organ
that checks on the circulation of the fluids in its own way. The whole
matter was inverted. One no longer saw the movement and inner vitality
of the fluids, or the etheric body active therein. The heart became a
mechanical apparatus and has remained so to this day for the majority of
physiologists and medical men.
The iatrochemists still had some faint knowledge concerning the
etheric body. There was full awareness of it in what Galen described. In
van Helmont or Paracelsus there was still an inkling of the etheric
body, more than survived in the official iatrochemists who conducted the
schools of that time. In the iatromechanists no trace whatsoever
remained of this ether body; all conception of it had vanished into tin
air. Man was seen only as a physical body, and that only to the extent
that he consists of solid parts. These were now dealt with by means of
physics, which had in the meantime also been cast out of the human
being. Physics was now applied externally to man, whom one no longer
understood. Man had been turned into an empty bag, and physics had been
established in an abstract manner. Now this same physics was reapplied
to man. Thus one no longer had the living being of man, only an empty
bag stuffed with theories.
It is still this way today. What modern physiology or anatomy tells
us of man is not man at all, it is physics that was cast out of man and
is now changed around to be fitted back into man. The more intimately we
study this development, the better we see destiny at work. The
iatrochemists had a shadowy consciousness of the etheric body, the
iatromechanists had none. Then came a man by the name of Stahl
[79] who, considering his time, was an unusually clever
man. He had studied iatrochemistry, but the concepts of the "inner
fermentation processes" seemed inadequate to him because they only
transplanted externalized chemistry back into the human bag. With the
iatromechanists he was still more dissatisfied because they only placed
external mechanical physics back into the empty bag. No knowledge, no
tradition existed concerning the etheric body as the driving force of
the moving fluids. It was not possible to gain information about it. So
what did Stahl do? He invented something, because there was nothing left
in tradition. He told himself: the physical and chemical processes that
go on in the human body cannot be based on the physics and chemistry
that are discovered in the external world. But he had nothing else to
put into man Therefore he invented what he called the "life
force," the "vital force," With it he founded the
dynamic school. Stahl was gifted with a certain instinct. He felt the
lack of something that he needed; so he invented this "vital
force." The Nineteenth Century had great difficulty in getting rid
of this concept. It was really only an invention, but it was very hard
to rid science of this "life force."
Great efforts were made to find something that would fit into this
empty bag that was man. This is why men came to think of the world of
machines. They knew how a machine moves and responds. So the machine was
stuffed into the empty bag in the form of L'homme machine by La
Mettrie. [80] Man is a
machine. The materialism, or rather the mechanics, of the Eighteenth
Century, such as we see in Holbach's Systeme de la nature,
[81] which Goethe so detested in his
youth, reflects the total inability to grasp the being of man with the
ideas that prevailed at that time in outer nature. The whole Nineteenth
Century suffered from the inability to take hold of man himself.
But there was a strong desire somehow or other to work out a
conception of man. This led to the idea of picturing him s a more highly
evolved animal. Of course, the animal was not really understood either,
since physics, chemistry, and psychology, all in the old sense, are
needed for this purpose even if pneumatology is unnecessary. But nobody
realized that all this is also required in order to understand the
animal. One had to start somewhere, so in the Eighteenth Century man was
compared to the machine and in the Nineteenth Century he was traced back
to the beast. All this is quite understandable from the historical
standpoint. It makes good sense considering the whole course of human
evolution. It was, after all, this ignorance concerning the being of man
that produced our modern opinions about man. The development towards
freedom, for example, would never have occurred had the ancient
experience of physics, chemistry, psychology, and pneumatology survived.
Man had to lose himself as an elemental being in order to find himself
as a free being. He could only do this by withdrawing from himself for a
while and paying no attention to himself any longer. Instead, he
occupied himself with the external world, and if he wanted theories
concerning his own nature, he applied to himself what was well suited
for a comprehension of the outer world. During this interim, when man
took the time to develop something like the feeling of freedom, he
worked out the concepts of science; these concepts that are, in a manner
of speaking, so robust that they can grasp outer nature. Unfortunately,
however, they are too coarse for the being of man, since people do not
go to the trouble of refining these ideas to the point where they ca
also grasp the nature of man. Thus modern science arose, which is well
applicable to nature and has achieved great triumphs. But it is useless
when it comes to the essential being of man.
You can see that I am not criticizing science. I am only describing
it. Man attains his consciousness of freedom only because he is no
longer burdened with the insights that he carried within himself and
that weighed him down. The experience of freedom came about when man
constructed a science that in its robustness was only suited to outer
nature. Since it does not offer the whole picture and is not applicable
to man's being, this science can naturally be criticized in turn. It is
most useful in physics; in chemistry, weak points begin to show up; and
psychology becomes completely abstract. Nevertheless, mankind had to
pass through an age that took its course in this way in order to attain
to an individually modulated moral conception of the world and to the
consciousness of freedom. We cannot understand the origin of science if
we look at it only from one side. It must be regarded as a phenomenon
parallel to the consciousness of freedom that is arising during the same
period, along with all the moral and religious implications connected
with this awareness.
This is why people like Hobbes
[82] and Bacon, who were
establishing the ideas of science, found it impossible to connect man to
the spirit and soul of the universe. In Hobbes' case, the result was
that, on the one hand, he cultivated the germinal scientific concepts in
the most radical way, while, on the other hand, he cast all spiritual
elements out of social life and decreed "the war of all against
all." He recognized no binding principle that might flow into
social life from a super-sensible source, and therefore he was able,
though in a somewhat caricatured form, to discuss the consciousness of
freedom in a theoretical way for the first time.
The evolution of mankind does not proceed in a straight line. We
must study the various streams that run side by side. Only then can we
understand the significance of man's historical development.
∴
Lecture IX
6 January 1923, Dornach
It is in the nature of the case that the subject of a lecture course
like this one is inexhaustible. Matters could be elaborated and looked
at more thoroughly. But since, unfortunately, we must come to an end, we
have to be content with given guidelines and indication. Today,
therefore, I shall only supplement the scanty outlines and hints already
discussed to that in a certain sense the picture will be rounded
out.
Proceeding once again from the being of man as viewed by spiritual
science, we must say that we member man into physical body, etheric or
formative forces body, astral body (which essentially represents the
soul life) and ego. Let us be clear that properly speaking the physical
body resides only in the small part of the human organization that we
can describe as solid and sharply defined. On the other hand, all that
pertains to liquid or fluid forms is taken hold of by the etheric body
in such a way that it is in a constant process of blending, separating,
combining, and dissolving. It is in perpetual flux. Then there are the
gaseous, aeriform elements, such as are active in oxygen and other
gases. In these, the astral body is at work. Finally, the ego
organization is active in everything that has to do with warmth.
What I have just outlined cannot, however, be reduced to a diagram.
We must clearly understand, for instance, that because the formative
forces body pulsates through all fluid and liquid elements of the body,
it also sweeps along the solid substances. Everything in the human
organization is in close interaction, in constant interplay. We must
always be aware of that. But now let us also remember that this human
organization has been experienced in different ways in the course of
evolution. This was one of the main themes of these lectures.
What is described today as the subject matter of external physics or
mechanics, was originally attained through an inward experience of the
physical body. Our present-day physics contains statements that
originated because there once existed an internally experienced physics
of the physical body. As I have explained a number of times, this inward
physics was divorced from man and now continues to function merely as a
science that observes outer nature. During the decline of the medieval
alchemy the same thing happened with what lives inwardly in man by
virtue of the etheric body. The work of this body in the fluids was once
experienced, but now it is only dimly perceptible in the fantastic,
alchemistic formulas that we find in ancient writings. Originally this
was intelligent science, but inwardly experienced within the etheric. In
a way, this is still in the process of being divorced from man, because
as yet we really do not have a fully developed chemistry. We have many
chemical processes in the world that we seek to understand, but only in
a physical and mechanical way.
In the beginning man experienced all this inwardly by means of his
organization, but in the course of time he cast it all out of himself.
In this process of casting out all our science developed, from astronomy
to the meager beginnings of modern chemistry. On the other hand,
thinking, feeling and willing, the subject matter of abstract psychology
(which today is no longer considered real) was in former times actually
not experienced inside man. Man felt himself at one with the external
world outside his own being, when he experienced the soul life. Thus
what was corporeal was once experienced inwardly, whereas the soul
element was experienced by leaving one's being and communing with the
outer world. Psychology was once the science of that aspect of the world
that affects man in such a way that he appears to himself as a soul
being. Physics and chemistry were cast out of man, whereas psychology
and pneumatology (which I shall discuss directly) were stuffed into him
and lost their reality. They turned into subjective perceptions with
which nothing could be done.
What was experienced together with the cosmos through the astral
body (which leaves us in sleep) has become the subject of psychology.
What man experienced as spirit in union with the universe was
pneumatology. Today, as I have already pointed out, this has shrunk down
to the idea of the ego or to a mere feeling. Therefore we now have as
science of external nature what was once inner experience, while our
science of man's inner nature is what was once external experience.
Now we must call to mind what is needed, on the one hand for physics
and chemistry, and on the other for psychology and pneumatology, in
order to develop them further in a conscious way, since man today finds
himself in the age of the development of the consciousness soul. Take
physics, for example, which in recent times has become mostly abstract
and mechanical. From all that I have said you will have seen that the
scientific age has increasingly felt impelled to restrict itself to the
externally observed mechanics of space. Long ago, man accompanied motion
by means of inward experience and judged it according to what he felt
within as movement. Observing a falling stone, he experienced its inner
impulse of movement in his own inner human nature, in his physical body.
This experience, after the great casting out, led to the measuring of
the rate of fall per second. In our attitude toward nature, the idea
prevails that what is observed is what is real.
What can be observed in the outer world? It is motion, change of position.
[83]
As a rule, we let velocity vanish neatly in a differential
coefficient. But it is motion that we observe, and we express
velocity as movement per second, hence by means of space. This means,
however, that with our conscious experience, we are entirely outside
the object. We are not involved in it in any way when we merely watch
its motion, meaning its change of position in space. We can do that
only if we find ways and means to inwardly take hold of the spatial,
physical object by an extending of the same method with which we
separated from it in the first place. Instead of the mere movement,
the bare change of position, we have to view the velocity in the
objects as their characteristic element. Then we can know what a
particular object is like inwardly, because we find velocity also
within ourselves when we look back upon ourselves.
This is what is necessary. The trend of scientific development in
regard to the outer physical world must be extended in the direction
of proceeding from mere observation of motion to a feeling for the
velocity possessed by a given object. We must advance from motion to
velocity. That is how we enter into reality. Reality is not taken
hold of if all we see is that a body changes its position in space.
But if we know that the body possesses an inner velocity-impulse,
then we have something that lies in the nature of the body. We assert
nothing about a body if we merely indicate its change of position,
but we do state something about it when we say that it contains
within itself the impulse for its own velocity. This then is a
property of it, something that belongs to its nature. You can
understand this by a simple illustration. If you watch a moving
person, you know nothing about him. But if you know that he has a
strong urge to move quickly, you do know something about him.
Likewise, you know something about him, when you know that he has a
reason for moving slowly. We must be able to take hold of something
that has significance within a given body. It matters little
whether or not modern physics speaks, for example, of atoms; what
matters is that when it does speak of them it regards them as
velocity charges. That is what counts.
Now the question is: how do we arrive at such a perception? We can
discuss the best in the case of physics, since today's
chemistry has advanced too little. We have to become clear about what
we actually do when, in our thinking, we cast inwardly experienced
mechanics and physics into external space. That is what we are doing
when we say: The nature of what is out there in space is of no
concern to me; I observe only what can be measured and expressed in
mechanical formulas, and I leave aside everything that is not
mechanical. Where does this lead us? It leads us to the same process
in knowledge that a human being goes through when he dies. When he
dies, life goes out of him, the dead organism remains. When I begin
to think mechanistically, life goes out of my knowledge. I then have
a science of dead matter. We must be absolutely clear that we are
setting up a science of dead matter so long as the mechanical and
physical aspect is the sole object of our study of nature. You must
be aware that you are focusing on what is dead. You must be able to
say to yourself: The great thing about science is that it has
tacitly resolved that, unlike the ancient alchemists who still saw in
outer nature a remnant of life, it will observe what is dead I
minerals, plants, and animals. Science will study only what is dead
in them, because it utilizes only ideas and concepts suitable for
what is dead. Therefore, our physics is dead by its nature.
Science will stand on a solid basis only when it fully realizes that
its mode of thinking can take hold only of the dead. The same is true
of chemistry, but I cannot go into that today because of the lack of
time.
When we look only at motion and lose sight of velocity, we are
erecting a physics that is dead, the end-product of living things is
then our concern, and the end-product is death. Hence, when we look
at nature with the eyes of modern mechanics and physics, we must
realize that we are looking at a corpse.
Nature was not always like this. It was different at one time. If I
look at a corpse, it would be foolish to believe that it was always
in this condition. The fact that I realize that it is a corpse proves
to me that once it was a living organism. The moment you realize that
modern mechanics and physics lead you to view nature in this way, you
will see that nature is now a corpse so far as physics is concerned.
We are studying a corpse.
Can we attain to something living, or at least an approach to it? The
corpse is the final condition of something living. Where is the
beginning condition? Well, my dear friends, there is no way to
rediscover velocity by observing motion. You may stare at
differential coefficients as long as you will but you will not find
it. Instead, you must turn back to man. Whereas formerly he
experienced himself from within, you must now study him from without
through his physical organism, and you must understand that in man
—
and especially in his physical and etheric organizations — the
beginning of a living condition must be sought.
No satisfactory form of physics and chemistry will be attained save
through a genuine science of man. But I expressly call attention to
the fact that such a genuine anthropology will not be reached by
approaching man with the methods of present-day physics and
chemistry. That would only carry death back into man and make his
body (his lower organization) even more dead than before.
You must study what is living in man, and not revert to the method of
physics and chemistry. What is needed are the methods that can be
found through spiritual-scientific research. Briefly stated,
spiritual-scientific research will meet the historic requirements of
natural science.
This historic requirement can be put in the following words: Science
has reached the point of observing what is corpse-like in nature.
Anthroposophical spiritual science must discover in addition to this
the beginning of a living condition. This has been preserved in man.
In former periods of evolution it was also externally perceptible. At
one time, the processes of nature were totally different. Today, we
walk around on the corpses of what existed in the beginning. But in
the two lower bodies of man, the beginning condition has been
preserved. There we can discover all that once existed, right back
to the Saturn condition. An historical approach leads beyond the
present state of science. It is quite clear why this is so. We are in
the midst of a period of development. If, as is so frequently the
case, we consider today's manner of thinking to be the most
advanced and do not realize that the real course of events was very
different, then we are looking at history the wrong way. As an
example, a twenty-five year old person need not only be observed in
the light of the twenty-five years that he has been alive, —
one must also observe the element in him that makes it possible for
him to live on. That is one point.
Movement:
Velocity:
Dead Aspect (Final Condition of
Being)
Phenomenon:
Being:
Semblance (Initial Condition of
Being)
The other point is that our psychology has become very thin, while
pneumatology has nearly reached the vanishing point. Again, we must
know how far it has gone with these two sciences in the present age.
If one speaks today of blue or red, of C-sharp or G, or of qualities
of warmth, he will say that they are subjective sensations. That is
the popular attitude; But what is a mere subjective sensation? It is
a "phenomenon." Just as we observe only motions in outer
nature, we study only the phenomenon in psychology and pneumatology.
And just as velocity is missing from motion in our external
observation, the essential thing — the living essence —
is missing from our observation of the inner soul life. Because we
only study phenomena and no longer experience the living essence, we
never get beyond mere semblance. The way thinking, feeling and
willing are experienced today, they are mere semblance. Modern
epistemologists have the man who wants to lift himself up by his own
pigtail, or like the man in a railroad car who pushes against the
wall without realizing that he cannot move the carriage in this way.
This is how modern epistemologists look. They talk and talk, but
there is no vitality in their talk because they are locked into the
mere semblance.
I have tried to put a certain end to this talk. The first time was in
my
Philosophy of Freedom,
[84]
where I demonstrated how this
semblance, inherent in pure thinking, becomes the impulse of freedom
when inwardly grasped by man in thinking. If something other than
semblance were contained in our subjective experience, we could never
be free. But if this semblance can be raised to pure thinking, one
can be free, because what is not real being cannot determine us,
whereas real being would do so. This was my first effort. My second
effort was at the Philosophical Congress in Bologna, when I analyzed
the matter psychologically. I attempted to show that our sensations
and thoughts are in fact outward experiences, rather than inward
ones, and that this insight can be attained by careful
observation.
These indications will have to be understood. Then, we shall realize
that we must rediscover being in semblance, just as we must
rediscover velocity in movement. Then, we will understand what this
inwardly experienced semblance really is. It will reveal itself as
the initial state of being. Man experiences this semblance;
experiences himself as semblance and as such lives his way into
semblance and thus transforms it into the seed of future worlds. I
have often pointed out that from our ethics, our morals, born of the
physical world of semblance, future physical worlds will arise, just
as from today's seed the plant will grow.
[85]
We are dealing with
the nascent state of being. In order to have a proper natural
science, we must realize that psychology and pneumatology must
understand what they observe as nascent states of being. Only then
will they throw light on those matters that natural science wants to
illuminate. But what is this "nascent" or "initial
state?"
Now this nascent state is in the outer world, not within. It is what
I see when I behold the green tapestry of plants, the world of colors
— red, green and blue — and the sounds that are out
there. What are these fleeting formations that modern-day physics,
physiology and psychology regard only as subjective? They are the
elements from which the worlds of the future create themselves. Red
is not engendered by matter in the eye or the brain, red is the
first, semblance-like, seed of future worlds.
If you know this, you will also want to know something about what
will correspond in these future worlds to the corpse-like element. It
will not be what we found earlier in our physics and chemistry, it
will be the corpse of the future. We shall recognize what will be the
corpse of the future, the future element of death, if we discover it
already today in the higher organization of man, where astral body
and ego are active. By experiencing the final condition there in
reference to the initial one, we at last gain a proper comprehension
of the nervous system and the brain insofar as they are dead, not
alive. In a certain sense, they can be more dead than a corpse,
inasmuch as they transcend the absolute point of death —
especially in the case of the nervous system — and become
"more
dead than dead." But this very fact makes the nervous system
and the brain bearers of the so-called spiritual element —
because the dead element dwells in them, the final state not yet even
reached by outer nature — because they even surpass this final
state.
In order to find psychology and pneumatology in the outer world, we
shall have to discover how the inanimate, the dead, dwells in the
human organism; namely, in the head organization and in part of the
rhythmic organization, mainly that of breathing. We must look at our
head and say of it that it is constantly dying. If it were alive, the
growing, sprouting living matter could not think. But because it
gives up life and constantly dies, the soul-spiritual thoughts,
endowed with being, have the opportunity to spread out over what is
dead as new living, radiant semblance.
You see, here lie the great tasks that, by means of the historical
manner of observation result quite simply from natural science. If we
don't take hold of them, we move like ghosts through the
present development of science, and not with the consciousness that
an epoch that has begun must find a way to continue. You can imagine
that much of this is contained implicitly in what science has
discovered. Scientific literature offers such indications everywhere.
But people cannot yet distinguish clearly; they like what is chaotic.
They don't care clearly to contemplate physics and chemistry on
one hand, and psychology and pneumatology on the other, because then
they would have to consider seriously the inner and outer aspects.
They prefer to vacillate in the murky waters between physics and
chemistry. Due to this, a bastard science has arisen that has become
the darling of natural research and even philosophy; namely,
physiology. As soon as the real facts are discovered, physiology will
fall apart into psychology on the one hand — a psychology that
is also a perception of the world — and on the other, into
chemistry, meaning a chemistry that is also a knowledge of man.
When these two are attained, this in-between science, physiology,
will vanish. Because today you have a morass in which you can find
everything, and because by juggling a bit to the left or the right,
it is possible to find a bit of a soul or a corporeal element, people
do quite well. The physiology of today is what above all must
disappear as the last remnant of former conceptions that have become
muddled. The reason physiological concepts are so abstruse is that
they contain soul and corporeal elements that are no longer
distinguished, thus they can play around with words and even juggle
the facts. One who aims for clear insight must realize that
physiology amounts in the end to fibbing with words and facts.
Until we admit this, we can't take the history of natural
science seriously. Science does not proceed only from undetermined
past ages to our time, it continues on from the present. History can
only be understood, if one comprehends the further course of things,
not in a superstitious, prophetic sense but by beginning now to do
the right thing. And infinitely much needs to be set right,
particularly in the domain of science. Natural science has grown
tall; it is like a nice teenager, who at the moment is going through
his years of unpolished adolescence, and whose guidance must be
continued so that he will become mature. Science will mature, if
murky areas like physiology disappear, and physics and pneumatology
arise again in the way outlined above. They will come into being, if
the anthroposophical way of thinking is applied in earnest to
science. This will be the case, when people feel that they are
learning something, when somebody speaks to them of a real physics, a
real chemistry, a real psychology and pneumatology; when they no
longer have the urge to comprehend everything concerning the world
and the human being through bastardized chaotic sciences like
physiology. Then, the development of human knowledge will once again
stand on a sound basis.
Naturally, therapy is particularly affected and suffers under
present-day physiology. You can well imagine this, because it works
with all manner of things that elude one's grasp, when one
begins to think clearly.
We cannot confront the great challenges of our time with a few
anthroposophical catchwords and phrases. It also does not suffice to
dabble with physiology on the borderline between psychology and
chemistry. The only way to proceed is to apply the methods of
spiritual-scientific anthroposophy to physics and chemistry. If you
are lazy — forgive me for this harsh expression, I don't
mean it in such a radical sense in this case — you say: These
matters can only be correctly judged, if one is clairvoyant.
Therefore I will wait until I am clairvoyant. I won't venture
to criticize physics and chemistry or even physiology.
My dear friends, you need not have insights that surpass ordinary
perception in order to know that a corpse is dead and that it must
have originated in life. Neither do you need to be clairvoyant in
order to analyze properly the true facts of today's physics and
chemistry, and to refer them back to their underlying living element,
once your attention is directed to the fact that this living element
is to be found by studying the "lower man." There you
will have the supplement you need for chemistry and physics. Make the
attempt, for once, really to study the mechanism of human movement.
[86]
Instead of constantly drawing axis of coordinates and putting the
movements into them apart from man; instead of multiplying
differential coefficients and integrals, make a serious attempt to
study the mechanics of movement in man. As they were once experienced
from within, so do you now study them from without. Then you will
have what you need, to add to your outer observation of nature, in
physics and chemistry.
In outer nature, those who proclaim atomism will always put you in
the wrong. They even work themselves up to the very spiritual
statement that when one speaks about matter in the sense of a modern
physicist, matter is no longer material. The physicists, themselves
are saying it;
[87]
our very opponents are saying it. In this case they
are right, and if we in our replies to them stop short at the
half-truths — that is to say, at the final conditions of being
— we shall never be equal to that which issues from them.
Here lie the tasks of the specialists, here lie the tasks of those
who have the requisite preliminary training, in one or another branch
of science.
Then we shall not establish a physicized or chemicized Anthroposophy,
but a true anthroposophical chemistry, anthroposophical physics. Then
we shall not establish a new medicine as a mere variation on the old,
but a true anthroposophical medicine.
The tasks are at hand. They are outlined in all directions. Just as
the simple heart can receive the observations that are scattered
everywhere in our lectures or lecture cycles, and that give spiritual
sustenance, so too the need is to take up on every hand the hints
that can lead us to the much-needed progress in the several domains
of science.
In the future, it will not suffice if man and nature do not again
become one. What physics and chemistry study in nature as the final
state of being, must be supplemented by the state of being in
"lower
man" belonging to the realm of physics and chemistry — in
man who is dependent on the physical and etheric bodies. It is
important that this be sought. It is not important to single out as
essential the valences of the structural formulas or the periodic law
in chemistry, because these are but schemata. While they are quite
useful as tools for counting and calculations, what matters is the
following realization. If the chemical processes are externally
observed, the chemical laws are not within them. They are contained
in the origin of chemical processes. Hence, they are found only, if,
with diligent effort, one tries to seek in the human being for the
processes that occur in his circulation, in the activity of his
fluids, through the actions of the etheric body. The explanation of
the chemical processes in nature lies in the processes of the etheric
body. These in turn are represented in the play of fluids in the
human organism and are accessible to precise study.
Anthroposophy poses a serious challenge in this direction. This is
why we have founded research institutes
[88]
in which serious, intensive
work must begin. Then the methods gained from anthroposophy can be
properly nurtured. This is also the main point of our medical
therapy; namely, that the old, confused physiology finally be
replaced with a real chemistry and psychology. Without this one can
never assert anything about the processes of illness and healing
in human nature, because every course of illness is simply an abnormal
psychological process, and each healing process is an abnormal chemical
process. Only to the extent that we know how to influence the chemical
process of healing
and how to grasp the psychological course of illness will we attain to
genuine pathology and therapy. This will emerge from the
anthroposophical manner of observation. If one does not want to
recognize this potential in anthroposophy, then one only wants
something a bit out of the ordinary and is unwilling to get to work
in earnest. Actually, everything that I have sketched here is only a
description of how the work should proceed, because a genuine
psychology and chemistry come into being through work. All the
prerequisites for this work already exist, because very man facts can
be found in scientific literature that researchers have accidentally
discovered but don't understand. Those of us who work in the
spirit of anthroposophy should take up these facts and contribute
something to their full comprehension. Take as an example what I
emphasized yesterday
[89]
in speaking to a smaller group of people. The
essential point about the spleen is that it is really an excretory
organ. The spleen itself is in turn an excretion of the functions in
the etheric body. Countless facts are available in medical literature
that need only be utilize — and that is the point: they should
be utilized — then the facts will be brought together
and what is needed will result.
A single person might accomplish this if a human life spanned six
hundred years. But by that time, other tasks would confront him and
his accomplishments would long since be outmoded. These things must be
attained through cooperation, through people working together. So
this is the second task — we must see to it that this becomes
possible. I believe that these tasks of the Anthroposophical Society
will emerge most clearly and urgently from a truly realistic study of
the history of natural science in recent times.
This history shows us at every turn that something great and
wonderful has arisen through modern science. In earlier times, the
truly inanimate dead aspects could never be discerned, hence, nothing
could be made of them. In those times inward semblance could never
really be observed; therefore, it couldn't be brought to life
by human effort, and hence, one couldn't arrive at freedom.
Today, we confront a grandiose world, which became possible only
because natural science studies the dead aspects. This is the world
of technology. Its special character can be discerned from the fact
that the word "technique" is taken from the Greek. There,
it still signifies "art," implying that art reveals,
where technology still contains spirit. Today, technology only
utilizes spirit in the sense of the abstract, spirit-devoid thoughts.
Technology could be achieved only by attaining a proper knowledge of
what is dead. Once in the course of humanity's evolution it was
necessary to concentrate upon the dead; it thus entered into the
realm of technology. Today, man stands in the midst of this realm of
technology that surrounds him on all sides. He looks out on it and
realizes that here at last is a sphere in which there is no spirit in
the proper sense. In regard to the spiritual element, it is important
that in all areas of technology human beings experience this inner
feeling, almost akin to one of pain over the death of a person. If
feeling and sensation can be developed in knowledge, then such a
feeling will arise, somewhat like the sensation one experiences when
a person is dying and one sees the living organism turn into a
corpse. Alongside the abstract indifferent cold knowledge, such a
feeling will arise through the true realization that technology is
the processing of the inanimate, the dead. This feeling will become
the most powerful impetus to seek the spirit in new directions.
I could well imagine the following view of the future: Man looks out
over the chimneys, the factories, the telephones — everything
that technology has produced in wondrous ways in the most recent
times. He stands atop this purely mechanical world, the grave of all
things spiritual, and he calls out longingly into the universe —
and his yearning will be fulfilled. Just as the dead stone yields the
living fiery spark if handled correctly, so from our dead technology
will emerge the living spirit, if human beings have the right
feelings about what technology is.
On the other hand, one need only understand clearly what pure
thinking is; namely the semblance from which can be brought forth the
most powerful moral impulses — those individual moral impulses
that I have described in my
Philosophy of Freedom.
Then, in a new way, man will face the feeling that was once confronted by
Nicholas Cusanus and Meister Eckhart. They said: When I life myself beyond
everything that I am ordinarily accustomed to observe, I come to
"nothingness" with all that I have learned. But in this
"nothingness" there arises for me the "I." If
man really penetrates to pure thinking, then he finds in it the
nothingness that turns into the I and from which emerges the whole
wealth of ethical actions, that will create new worlds. I can imagine
a person who first lets all knowledge of the preset, as inaugurated
by natural science, impress itself on him and then (centuries after
Meister Eckhart and Nicholas Cusanus) turns his gaze inward and with
today's mode of thinking arrives at the nothingness of his
inner life. In it, he discovers that the spirit really speaks to him.
I can imagine that these two images merge. On the one hand, man goes
to the place where barren technology has left the spirit behind.
There he calls out into cosmic expanses for the spirit. On the other
hand, he stops, thinks and looks within himself. And here, out of his
inner being, he receives the divine answer to the call he sent out
into the distances of the universe.
When we learn, through a new, anthroposophically imbued natural
science, to let the calls of infinite longing for the spirit, sent
out into the world, resound in our inner being, then this will be the
right starting point. Here, through an "anthroposophized"
inner perception, we will find the answer to the yearning call for
the spirit, desperately sounded out into the universe.
I did not want to describe the development of natural science in
recent times in a merely documentary fashion. Rather, I wanted to
show you the standpoint of a human being, who comprehends this
natural-scientific development and, in a difficult moment of
humanity's evolution, knows the right things to say to himself
in regard to the progress of mankind.
∴
Appendix: Book review by Bobby Matherne (1940 - 2019)
This is a review of the print version of the book published in 1985 by Matherne in 2003.
In the final words of these lectures, Steiner tells us that he "did not want to describe the
development of natural science in recent times in a merely documentary fashion." Instead he wanted
to show us "the standpoint of a human being who comprehends this natural-scientific development
and, in a difficult moment of humanity's evolution, knows the right things to say to himself in regard
the progress of mankind." I could not find better words in myself to summarize the theme of this
wonderful book than he did in closing his lecture series. Do you, dear Reader, know the "right things
to say" during this moment of humanity's evolution as regards the progress of humankind? Why
should anyone care? What's this evolution stuff about anyway - didn't that stop when man evolved
from apes? Isn't our science today the best science of all possible sciences? (From Voltaire's Candide, "Don't we live in the best of all possible worlds?") All very good questions
and ones that Steiner addresses in this lecture series.
As for the question about the best of all sciences, Owen Barfield aptly handles that one in his
Introduction when he talks about the Steiner's lectures contained in this book:
[page viii] Their basic argument is that modern science, and the scientism based
on it, so far from being the only possible 'reality-principle' is merely one way
of conceiving the nature of reality; a way moreover that has arisen only recently
and which there is no reason to suppose will last forever.
There was a dichotomy that occurred in the 15th Century between man and nature and our
progress in science to date has depended on that dichotomy in order to proceed. Along the way
humanity found itself discovering mathematical truths that later nested into physical truths about the
world we live in. Barfield tells us that Steiner "found an answer to a question which has puzzled
many thinkers: why should mathematics, a seemingly artificial construction of the human brain, have
been found an effective key to unlock so many of the secrets of nature?" (page xi) What we are to
find is that our fall from "psychic participation in life" was precipitated by the same mathematical
mode of thought that will be instrumental in leading us back to a reunion with that same fullness of
life. Barfield tells us to expect more details about that aspect in Steiner's lectures published in The
Boundaries of Natural Science, which volume is next on my agenda to read and review.
One might expect that Steiner would demean science in these lectures and one would be all
wet if one did. On the contrary he leads us to perceive in our modern scientific perceptions the seeds
of a new spirituality, and the fruits of a freedom that we could not have achieved but for the scientific
path we have trod for almost six centuries.
[page 2] My opinion, based on objective study, is that the scientific path taken
by modern humanity was, if rightly understood, not erroneous but entirely
proper.
Something important was lost to humanity around the year 1453; what was previously
accessible by humankind as shining spirit suddenly returned nothing. This thought occurred to
Cusanus (Nicolas of Cusa) while sailing home from Constantinople looking up at the stars. He later
wrote about this thought in his book, Docta Ignorantia or On Learned Ignorance. Meister Eckhart
also expressed this same thought as, "In all eternity, I must fetch the I from the 'nothingness' of
God." In Eckhart's original German writing, there is a parallel literal meaning: the word ich (I) can
be fetched from the word Nichts (nothingness).
[page 9] If we go back into earlier times, we find that in former ages it was
possible, when the soul turned its gaze inward into itself, to behold the spirit
shining forth within.
Thomas Aquinas or John Scotus Erigena in an earlier time would have looked through their
soul and found their spirit, their immortal I shining within. Now it was no longer possible to do so.
Cusanus was led to nothingness when he sought his spirit, but, being a mathematician, he sought to
use his skills in that art to approach the world of spirit. At the same time a new world was
approaching humanity from the sensory world, and mathematics was to prove a sturdy bridge
between the two worlds: the spiritual world of mathematics and the sensory world of post-15th
Century humanity. We can catch a glimpse of modern science in its embryonic form in Cusanus
when he proclaimed in 1440, in Steiner's words (page 12), "We must conceive the spirit realm as
so far removed from human perception that even mathematics can approach it only with halting
symbols." A hundred years later modern science was born when in 1543 Copernicus was able to say
with eclat:
[page 12] "Conceive of mathematics as so powerful and reliable that it can force
the sense world into mathematical formulas that are scientifically
understandable."
In the second lecture Steiner takes us back to ancient Greece where the world of spirit was
already beginning to dim to human eyes. In the ancient peoples before Greece they felt themselves
pervaded by a spirit that fills the cosmos, they felt themselves to have a messenger from the spiritual
cosmos that they called their individual soul, and they felt themselves to have a physical body that
was an image of their soul. What formerly humanity had experienced in itself as a living spirit that fills
the cosmos, the Greeks could only experience as Logos. Steiner tells us how a lonely disciple of the
time would have expressed this experience:
[page 20] "I listen to the silent universe and fetch this Logos-bearing soul out of
the silence. I love the Logos because the Logos brings tidings of an unknown
god."
The 'unknown god' is the Nichts or nothingness of Meister Eckhart. One result of this
devolution of spirit is that the soul moved from being the messenger of spirit to the bearer or carrier
of an image of the spirit. The body declined from image of spirit to a force. From this, Steiner says,
"The concept of force emerged." Force is one of those things that Newton took for granted that
everyone understood and declared them to be postulates from which he started. The world of spirit
and soul had become more tenuous and the body became more robust. Forces were seen everywhere
in the world and the body. Nature began to be something foreign from man. (Paraphrased from page
21.) Soon the soul came to be experienced as the realm of ideas and the body as spatial corporeality.
Here's Steiner's excellent summary of the devolution in three phases:
[page 24] Once upon a time, in the first phase, the soul experienced the spirit's
archetype within itself. It saw itself as a the messenger of spirit. In the second
phase, the soul inwardly experienced the living image of God in the Logos, it
became the bearer of the Logos. Now, in the third phase, the soul becomes, as
it were, a vessel for ideas and concepts. These may have the certainty of
mathematics, but they are only ideas and concepts.
We have now reached the phase in the 21st Century where the soul comprises the subjective
world of our thought and ideas and the body, the objective world of space, time, mass, motion, and
forces. This devolution of spirit or progression into scientific thinking is placed in historical time by
Steiner thus:
[page 27] We see how the first phase extends to the Eighth Century B. C., to the
ancient sage of Southern Europe whom I have described today. The second
extends from him to Nicholas Cusanus. We find ourselves in the third phase
now. The first is pneumatological, directed to the spirit in its primeval form.
The second is mystical, taking the world in the broadest sense possible. The
third is mathematical. . . The age of mathematizing natural science proceeds
from Cusanus into our time and continues further.
What are we doing today when we use mathematics to express in Cartesian coordinates the
three dimensions of space? We are using a way of thinking that is thought-out but not experienced.
How would one experience the three dimensions of space? Is that even necessary to consider? If we
wish to understand the origins of natural science, it is.
[page 30] Man would have never thought of these [three perpendicular
dimensions of space]if he had not experienced a threefold orientation within
himself. One orientation that man experiences in himself is from front to back.
We need only recall how, from the external modern anatomical and
physiological point of view, the intake and excretion of food, as well as other
processes in the human organism, take place from front to back. . . . I do
something with my right arm and make a corresponding move with my left arm.
Here, the processes are oriented to left and right. Finally, in regard to the last
orientation, man grows into it during earthly life. In the beginning he crawls on
all fours and only gradually stands upright, so that this last orientation flows
within him from above downward and up from below.
My wife experiences the three dimensions in this way, which is dramatically different from
the bare, bleak mathematical space layout of analytic geometry that her husband was trained in
during his college courses studying for his degree in physics. If Steiner's analysis of the experiencing
of spatial coordinates from within oneself is too abstract and unreal, he leads us to consider the
origin of numbers, such as the number two, which comes from the German word zwei [tsvei]. It is
rooted in the processes of entzweien, to "cleave in twain" and zweifeln, "to doubt" or to be two minds
of. Our words "double" and "twin" can be seen to originate from doubt and twain.
[pages 32, 33] It is not mere imitation of an external process when the number
two, zwei, is described by the word Entzweien, which indicates the disuniting,
the splitting, of something formerly a whole. It is in fact something that is
inwardly experienced and only then made into a scheme.
If we wish to discover this former way of experiencing reality inward, we have only to go
back to the writings of Rene Descartes and Baruch Spinoza. No doubt some of you have already read
their writings and are of the opinion that no such description exists in their writings. If so, perhaps you were looking to find the new (your way of thinking) in the old when you read them. Steiner leads us rather to understand how to find in the old (their way of thinking) the beginnings of what we call the new.
[page 33] Immerse yourself in these thinkers, not superficially as is the practice
today when one always wants to discover in the thinkers of old the modern
concepts that have been drilled into our heads, but unselfishly, putting yourself
mentally in their place. You will find that even Spinoza still retained something
of a mystical attitude toward the mathematical method.
Steiner says that running in a triangle gives one a completely different experience in the
blood from running in a square. During the pre-Renaissance time when "soul still felt movement as
a mathematical experience and blood as a mystical experience" no one could have conceived of the
orbits of the planets traversing a system of abstract coordinates. In the time of Harvey, a
contemporary of Francis Bacon, the circulation of the blood was beginning to be understood as
physical circulation with the heart in the center, just as the planets were soon to be understood as a physical
circulation with the Sun in the center. The very idea of the Renaissance as an abstract label applied
to a confluence of new ideas, of new ways of interpreting what had formerly been a direct inner
experience, was made possible by humanity developing the ability to divorce concepts from a direct
experience of the blood. The idea of the Renaissance just being a period of history just sitting back
in time is like the Copernican coordinates divorced from the heart experience just sitting out in
space. R. G. Collingwood said that all history is the history of thought. One can see that, not only was natural science affected by this dramatic change in 1453 AD, but even the way we understand history became changed in the process.
Geometrical and arithmetic forms were once experienced directly in the blood as intense
inner experiences. But an amazing thing happened during the Renaissance when abstract coordinates
replaced humanity's concept of direct inner experiences.
[page 43] This conception could change into a different one only when men lost
their awareness that everything quantitative - including mathematics - is
originally experienced by man in direct connection with the universe.
When a mathematician or physicist today has an insight and expresses it in a mathematical
formula, they have had a supersensible experience which they communicate to others in a communal
language (mathematics). They wonder in amazement when later the real world is found to line-up
with their mathematically described world! The reason for amazement can be described simply: the
supersensible world is always aligned with the material world or what they call the real world. Steiner
helps us, at last, to unravel the knots of this puzzle.
[page 44] The most that can be said of such an imposition of mathematics on
natural phenomena is that what has first been mathematically thought out is
then found to fit the phenomena of nature. But why this is so can no longer be
discovered within this particular world perception.
Steiner describes how Giordano Bruno experienced the Copernican world conception in the
old way, within his own being and points to Isaac Newton as the first to truly describe the new
conception of the world based on abstract mathematics. As such Steiner takes his place alongside
Dr. Andrew J. Galambos in paying respect to Newton for being the originator of modern science.
[pages 47, 48] Newton is pretty much the first to approach the phenomena of
nature with abstract mathematical thinking. Hence, as a kind of successor to
Copernicus, Newton becomes the real founder of modern scientific thinking.
[page 50] In fact, in Newton's physics we meet for the first time ideas of nature
that have been completely divorced from man. . . . By Newton's time
mathematics has become abstracted. Man has forgotten that originally he
received mathematics as an inspiration from God.
Later Newton was to feel uncomfortable with his tearing man completely away from the
spirit, and in his book Optics talked about space as the "sensorium of God." Bishop Berkeley in a
similar manner rejected the ideas of infinitesimals, regarding them as a loss of reality, since the only
thing that existed for him was what could be experienced. The mathematical processes of
differentiating and integrating, in Steiner's view, are similar to what one might do if one were to
chop a living human body into small pieces (differentiate) and then place the pieces back together
as if it were a jigsaw puzzle (integrate).
[pages 54,55] To differentiate is to kill; to integrate is to piece the dead together
again in some kind of framework, to fit the differentials together again into a
whole. But they do not thereby become alive again, after having been
annihilated. One ends up with dead spectres, not with anything living.
One might think that Steiner had little respect for science, but that would be wrong. He had
a great respect for and understanding of the evolution of consciousness. He knew that people "like
to regard as great thinkers those men who have said something or that they approve. But if the great
men also said something they do not approve, they feel very superior and think: Unfortunately, on
this point he wasn't as enlightened as I am." (pages 56,57) Having grown up in a culture completely
divorced from the spirit since the last vestiges of understanding spirit disappeared with Bruno,
Berkeley, and Newton, we exude a hubris about our world, up until now. It does not serve us well. Unless we let
go of our myopic attitude of superiority, we will not be able to find collectively the spirit in nature,
that same spirit that each of us will find individually upon our death. What is the value of science
as we know today, according to Steiner?
[page 57] Things that can only be learned from a corpse cannot be learned by
a person who is unwilling to examine the corpse. Therefore certain mysteries of
the world can be comprehended only if the modern scientific way of thinking is
taken seriously. . . . The scientific world view must be taken seriously, and for
this reason I was never an opponent of it; on the contrary, I regarded it as
something that of necessity belongs to our time. . . . It was the misinterpretation
of such scientific discoveries that I opposed.
One example of misinterpretation that Steiner describes in detail is the atomism of living
beings or the cell theory of Schleiden and Schwann in the early 19th Century. This atomism or
dividing things up into cells is equivalent to killing the very thing we're trying to understand,
namely, life. "The truth of the matter is that any real idea of organisms has been lost to the atomistic
approach." (page 70)
[page 81] Therefore, in spite of its great achievements we can say that science
owes its greatness to the fact that it has completely missed the essential nature
of man.
In case, you dear Reader, want evidence that we are still "missing the essential nature of
man" take a look at this quote from a well-known scientist of our day, Richard Dawkins: "If you
want to understand life, don't think about vibrant, throbbing gels and oozes, think about information
technology."
To help us understand our modern sciences of physics and chemistry, Steiner takes us back
for physics to our earlier understanding of motion in its internal human experience, for chemistry
to our internal human experience of "throbbing gels and oozes" to use Dawkins' derisive terms. The
Table below appears on page 93 and I've added for completeness the sciences of psychology and
pneumatology. The latter is the now defunct science of the spirit. Defunct I define operationally as:
cannot be found in the Encyclopedia Britannica or many dictionaries. It means the science of the
spirit, which Steiner says has been reduced to almost nothing, a jot in the footnotes of science today,
"the mere dot of the ego." (page 107) Physics is the most abstract science — it is the most separated from human
existence, and as a result, it consists of laws that are exact and universally applicable. Chemistry on
the other hand can never be completely separated from the gels and oozes of human life, and as such will
never be able to reach the status of physics because it is not "possible to take as much of the etheric
body into the external world as was accomplished in the physical body."
One way to interpret the above Table to take it as a key to understanding how knowledge of
the science in the fourth column amounts to an inner experience of the body listed in the third
column. Physics is the inner experience of our physical body abstracted mathematically into laws.
Chemistry is the inner experience of our etheric body abstracted to the degree possible into forms
approximating laws. Psychology, the inner experience of our Astral body of thoughts and feelings.
And Pneumatology, that almost non-existent science, the inner experience of our immortal spirit in
our "I" or Ego organization. Here's how Steiner describes the components of the Table.
[page 107] All this took the place of what had been experienced as a unity, when
men of old said: We have four elements, earth, water, air, and fire. Earth we
experience in ourselves when we experience the physical body. Water we
experience in ourselves when we experience the etheric body as the agent that
moves, mixes, and separates the fluids. Air is experienced when the astral body
is experienced in thinking, feeling, and willing, because these three are
experienced as surging with the inner breathing process. - Finally, warmth (or
fire, as it was then called) was experienced in the sensation of the ego.
The Four Sciences Table
Warmth
Blood
Ego Organization
Pneumatology
Air
Pneuma
Astral Body
Psychology
Water
Phlegm
Etheric Body
Chemistry
Earth
Black Gall
Physical Body
Physics
Again we find that our science of today is rife with misinterpretation of the human body. We
find wonderful photos of the organs of the body in full color, layered over one another so that one
can see how the organs are aligned in space from front to back. What's missing, however, is the
essential nature of the etheric body: the throbbing gels and flowing oozes.
[page 110] Laymen see the pictures and have the impression that this is all they
need to understand the body. But this is misleading. It is only one tenth of man.
The remainder ought to be described by drawing a continuous stream of fluids
interacting in the most manifold ways in the stomach, liver, and so forth. Quite
erroneous conceptions arise as to how man's organism actually functions,
because only the sharply outlined organs are observed.
So far, one might argue, Steiner has not said much that is good about modern science,
nothing that would indicate why he even respects it. Anyone who has read Steiner's classical book
The Philosophy of Freedom (1898) knows that freedom is something that Steiner knows something
about. Keep that in mind as you read his words about the impact that modern science has had on
freedom.
[page 114] The development towards freedom, for example, would never have
occurred had the ancient experience of physics, chemistry, psychology, and
pneumatology survived. Man had to lose himself as an elemental being in order
to find himself as a free being. He could only do this by withdrawing from
himself for a while and paying no attention to himself any longer. . . . During
this interim, when man took the time to develop something like the feeling of
freedom, he worked out the concepts of science; these concepts that are, in a
manner of speaking, so robust that they can grasp nature. Unfortunately,
however, they are too coarse for the being of man.
Science brought us to a feeling for freedom, but the very modes of thought that led us to
grasp the natural world in a robust manner were too coarse to allow us to understand the human
being, up until now. To truly understand science, we must look to the parallel evolution of our
consciousness and the freedom that accompanied it.
What's this all about? some of you may be asking. Where do we go from here with all these
insights into how science evolved to where it is by distancing itself from a direct experience of the
human being as much as possible?
[page 126] And infinitely much needs to be set right, particularly in the domain
of science. Natural science has grown tall; it is like a nice teenager, who at the
moment is going through his years of unpolished adolescence, and whose
guidance must be continued so that he will become mature.
This will only come about if the "anthroposophical way of thinking is applied to science."
What is needed is for people who are schooled in the natural sciences to learn to add anthroposophical ways of understanding the world to their school-taught knowledge of chemistry and physics. Just as ordinary perception is
enough to enable anyone to discern the difference between a corpse and a living human being, so
also ordinary perception is enough to allow one to "analyze properly the true facts of today's physics
and chemistry." (page 127)
When we cooperate to achieve this goal, we will return to our earlier understandings of the
world, but in a new way, infused with the insights of modern science and with the new-found
consciousness of freedom that we have evolved in the only way possible: by straying from our inner
experiences to develop a robust understanding of the world in which we live.
∴
Notes
◬
Rudolf Steiner, Mysticism at the Dawn of the
Modern Age (Blauvelt, NY: Steinerbooks, 1960) (formerly published as
Eleven European Mystics).
◬
These include the three natural scientific courses
held in Stuttgart: First First Scientific Lecture Course: Light
Course (Forest Row, England: Steiner Schools Fellowship, 1977);
Second Scientific Lecture Course: Warmth Course (Spring Valley,
NY: Mercury Press, 1981); and Das Verhältnis der verschiedenen
naturwissenschaftlichen Gebiete sur Astronomie. (Dornach,
Switzerland: Rudolf Steiner Verlag). The relationship between natural
science and spiritual science is dealt with in The Boundaries of
Natural Science (Spring Valley, NY, Anthroposophic Press,
1983).
◬
Nicholas Cusanus (Nicholas of Cusa),
1401–1464. Lawyer, churchman, philosopher, mathematician. Ordained
priest between 1436–1440, Cardinal 1448. Bishop of Brixen, 1450.
cf. chapter on Cusanus in Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern
Age.
◬
Nicholas Cusanus was made Cardinal and named Bishop
of Brixen in rapid succession. Though a stranger to Brixen he was named
Bishop there directly by the Pope. This led to a protracted conflict
with his diocese, during which the latter gathered behind the Duke of
Tirol. Cusa was ambushed by the Duke, imprisoned, and forced into
accepting a demeaning agreement. The Duke was excommunicated by the Pope
and attacked by the Swiss Confederation. However, he was supported by
German Counts and remained intransigent. Cusa died before the Emperor
could resolve the conflict. The battles around him did not rob Cusa of
his peace of mind, and he developed his philosophic, mathematical and
theological insights, writing fifteen of his works during the time in
Brixen.
◬Brethren of Common
Life (also of Good Will): Founded by Gerhart Groote around
1376. Brother-houses in Holland, Northern Germany, Italy and Portugal.
Brought into the Catholic Church in the Fifteenth Century. Their schools
taught under the strict observance of dogma.
◬Council of Basel: 1431–1449. Called by
Pope Martin V on July 23, 1431, the year of his death. This was the last
of four reformatory councils with the aim of ending the division in the
Church. There came a new rift in the Church.
◬
In
1437. This summarizes a long process: Cusanus entered the Council 1432
with the task from the Archdiocese of Trier to defend their Archbishop,
whom they had chosen against the will of the Pope. Through the treatise
De Concordantia Catholica (On Catholic Unity) which he
distributed among the Council and which contained an exceptional survey
of the decisions of the Councils and Decrees of the Church, he offered
the advice welcome by the majority that the Common Council was beyond
the Pope. Thus, he immediately became an important figure in the
Council.
Later, the Council majority and the history writings
accused Cusanus of having changed his conviction. But Cusanus' deep
understanding was ignored, which was rooted in his attitude and which
comes to expression in the following words: "When a decision is
made unanimously, then one can believe that it came from the Holy
Spirit. It lies not in men's power to meet somewhere, and although they
are so different from each other, they are able to come to a harmonious
decision. It is God's work." (From J.M. Duex, Der Deutsche
Cardinal Nicolaus Von Cusa, Regensburg 1874, Bd. 2, s. 262, which
has translated some of the most important of the De Concordantia
Catholica.) Cusanus must have experienced at the Council that his
description of the meaning of a Council was not taken with interest, and
he must have faced a decision that is mentioned in the
lecture.
◬
Pope Eugene 4th was put
down and Duke Amadeus of Savoy was set up as Pope Felix 5th in 1439. His
resignation in 1449 caused the disbandment of the Council.
◬
From 1439–1448
Cusanus acted on the order of the Pope as "Hercules of the
Eugenians" as an opponent called him. He went to worldly and
churchly princes as well as to the "Reichstag," and he tried
to overcome the neutrality of the Germans about the split of churches,
with complete success.
◬
At the
meetings of the princes, 1454, in Nuremberg, Regensburg, and Frankfurt
after the invasion of Constantinople by the Turkish, Cusanus tried to
motivate the princes to a crusade. After J. Hunnyadis' victory over the
Turkish Army in front of Belgrade in 1456 Cusanus organized, at the same
day he received the message, a festival of thanksgiving, and he spoke
the following words: "Because the lower man can only enjoy life
animal-like and physical, Satan who wants to destroy the Gospels in a
fine way, intended the appearance of Muhammad who knows the Gospel and
the Bible, to let him give the Gospel and Bible an animal-like, sensual
meaning. In this way Satan taught Muhammad knowledge to let go forth the
head of Malignity, the son of Ruin, and to be an enemy of the cross of
Christ." (From a sermon, "Landaus Invocalo
Dominum," partly translated by J.M. Duex A.A.O.S. 165).
Further sermons against the Turks are known from October 28, and
November 5 of the same year. (E. Varisteenberge, Le Cardinal Nicolas
De Cues, Paris 1920, S. 231 F, and index of sermons s. 480), but
this sermon seems to be available only in Latin.
Cusanus himself
announced his appointment as Cardinal with a short autobiographical note
in which is written: Nicolas was made Cardinal secretly by Pope Eugene
(Hist. Jahrbuch der Goerrers Gesellschaft 16.S.549).
◬De Pace Fidei (On the Peace of the
Faiths), written in September 1453. "The horrible days of
Constantinople ... had caused a deep feeling of sadness in the breast of
a man who once had wandered through this region, and caused him to sink
into deep contemplation, and he had a vision. In this sublime state, he
particularly thinks about the differences of the religions of the world,
and the possibility of their harmony. This harmony is, in his opinion, a
basic condition for religious peace." (Introduction to De Pace
Fidei: Nach Duex A.A.O.S. 405).
◬
Cusanus left Basel in May
1437 together with other representatives of the minority and traveled
for the minority with the legation of the Pope to Constantinople to
accompany the Greek Emperor and the heads of the Eastern Church to the
Union Council in Ferrara. They arrived in February 1438 in
Italy.
◬De Docta Ignorantia (The Learned
Ignorance). Three books finished in February 1440.
◬
Meister Eckhart: Hochheim by Gotha about
1260–before 1328, Cologne. Dominican, schoolmaster, German mystic.
Preached in leading posts in orders and churches; taught in Paris,
Strasbourg, Cologne. Main work: Opus Tripartius. Based on
Scholasticism and writings of Dionysius the Areopagite. Copies of his
sermons partly went around without his control. Meister Eckhart died,
accused as heretic, during the trial. See chapter, "Meister
Eckhart," in Rudolf Steiner's Mysticism at the Dawn of the
Modern Age.
◬
These
lines cannot be made clear and simple because the German text plays at
length on the words Nicht and Ich.
◬
Thomas Aquinas: Castle
Roccasecca in the Neopolitan region, about 1225–1274 Cloister
Fossanuova. Dominican, scholar, churchman. In Cologne, student and
friend of Albertus Magnus. Advocated the spiritual reality of general
concepts. He directed the theological school in Rome from
1261–1267. There the studies of the Dominican; from 1268 onwards
he is teaching in Naples and France. See Rudolf Steiner, The
Redemption of Thinking and Riddles of Philosophy (Spring
Valley, NY: Anthroposophic Press, 1973).
◬
Nicholas Copernicus: Thorn
1473–1543 Frauenburg. Humanist, mathematician, astronomer,
physician, lawyer. No publications during his life, with the exception
of a translation. Finished his work on the heliocentric planetary system
around 1507. Copernicus was already on his deathbed when his De
Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium was published. He dedicated it to
Pope Paul III. His friend and publisher introduced it as a purely
hypothetical, special scientific method of calculation. It thus slipped
past the censor, until the third edition was banned in 1616/17. Not
until 1822 was it accepted by the Catholic Church, cf. Rudolf Steiner,
The Spiritual Guidance of Man. (Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic
Press, 1983).
◬
Post-Atlantean Age: cf.
Rudolf Steiner, An Outline Of Occult Science (Spring Valley, NY:
Anthroposophic Press, 1984).
◬
A literal translation of the transcript would read:
"As body; and as body, as an image of the
spirit."
◬
I listen to the silent universe: cf. Rudolf
Steiner, Truth-Wrought Words. (Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic
Press, 1979).
◬
Democritus: c. 460–360 B.C. From his numerous
writings about philosophy, mathematics, physics, medicine, psychology,
and technology, only some fragments and an index remain. The remark
mentioned is a report from Aristotle, Metaphysics 1:4:
"That is why they (Leucippus and Democritus) say that the
non-existent exists just as much as the existent, just as emptiness is
just as good as fullness, and they posit these as material
causes."
◬
Francis Bacon: (also
Francis Bacon of Verulam), London 1561–1626 Highgate. Lawyer,
doctor, politician, diplomat, essayist, philosopher and humanist. The
leading English government liberal, successful during 1603–1621.
In these years his main work was developed. The philosophy of his age he
found stuck in hopeless experiments to solve insolvable problems with
Aristotelian logic. The only source of sure knowledge and abilities for
him was natural science. He saw a renewal of the spiritual and economic
life in this science. Principal works: Novum Organum an
inductive logic contradicting that of Aristotle (the old
Organum); De Dignitate et Augmentis Scientiarum; a Critical
Encyclopedia of all Science; Sylva Sylvarum: Preliminary Announcement of
Procedure and Method (this remained in preparation). His literary
success was astonishing, and it greatly furthered the materialistic
world view. cf. Riddles of Philosophy.
◬
Spinoza, Benedictus: Amsterdam 1632–1677. The
Hague. Philosopher, mathematician, had Humanistic and Talmudistic
training. By vocation, optician and politician. His main work
Ethics with the characteristic full title Ethica Ordine
Geometrica Demonstrata (Ethic Represented by Geometric
Method) could only be published by his friends after his death. See
Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern Age and Riddles of
Philosophy.
◬
René Descartes:
Lat., Renatus Cartenius, Le Haye (Tourraine) 1598–1650 Stockholm.
Mathematician, physicist, philosopher. Educated by the Jesuits in La
Fleche, he first became a soldier and was part of some campaigns but
turned away from outer life to enter into the loneliness of a striver
for knowledge, living first in Paris and then for a long time in
Holland. He died in Stockholm, having been called there by Queen
Christine. For him, doubt of tradition, but also of all sense
perception, was the starting point of his philosophy and he found in
self-consciousness the security of all being ("Cogito ergo
Sum"). He developed the method of analytical geometry and gave
an explanation of the rainbow. Main works: Essays, 1637, in it
"Discours de la Methode and Dioptiric,"
"Meditationes de Prima Philosophia," 1641;
"Passions de L'Ame," 1650. See Riddles of
Philosophy.
◬
Non-Euclidian geometry is
a prime example of "the self-contained inner ability to
think." C. Friedrich Gauss (1777–1855) discovered first that
one can think more than only a geometric system. Because nobody
understood this, he decided not to publish his results and to withdraw
from the fruitless quarrel. Independently of Gauss in 1828 N.I.
Lobatschewskij and in 1829 J. Boljai first published their solutions to
the same problem. Rudolf Steiner often spoke about the meaning of this
achievement, as in Wege und Ziele des geistigen Menschen in the
lecture "Der Heutige Stand der Philosophie und
Wissenschaft," (Dornach, Switzerland: Rudolf Steiner Verlag,
1973; GA Bibl. Nr. 125). See also: Georg Unger, Physic am
Scheidewege (Dornach: 1948), pages 19–28, and Vom Bielden
Physikalischer Begriffe, Vol. 3 (Stuttgart: 1967), pages 31–32
and 193–194.
◬
Johannes Tauler: About
1300–1361 Strasbourg. Preacher and pastor, Dominican, mystic,
student of Meister Eckhart. Sermons and writings in German by W.
Lehmann, 1923; see also Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern Age,
the chapter "Friendship with God."
◬
In a reply to two lectures, which Walter Johannes
Stein and Eugen Kolisko gave to defend two articles on
"Anthroposophy as Science" in the Goettingen newspaper, Hugo
Fuchs, Professor of Anatomy, spoke sarcastically of a human being with
head, breast, and belly system. (From a report of the newspaper Die
Dreigliederung des Sozialen Organismus, August 1920, No.
5).
◬
From Goethe's
Faust, Part I, the scene in the Student Room with Faust and
Mephisto. See Rudolf Steiner, The Occult Significance of the
Blood (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1967).
◬
William Harvey, 1578–1658, physiologist,
Professor of Anatomy, London, discoverer of the main bloodstream: De
Motu Cordis et Sanguinis (1628).
◬
Giordano Bruno: Nola 1548–1600 Rome.
Dominican, 1563–1576, a great traveler. Main works developed at
the English court at the time of Elizabeth I. After he returned to Italy
he was imprisoned because of heretical teachings, and was burned in Rome
after 8 years in prison. See Riddles of Philosophy, and The
Spiritual Guidance of Man, by Rudolf Steiner.
◬
Isaac Newton, Sir:
Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire 1642–1727 Kensington, London. Born as a
dwarf-like child. Grew up on a farm and went to village and small town
schools until 1661. After he was accepted at the University he was of
medium talent until his "flaming" as a genius physicist,
astronomer, mathematician 1663–1664. Professor in Cambridge
1669–1701, member of the Royal Society London 1662 and from 1703
until his death, its President. Main work: Law of Gravitation,
Mathematically Adapted to the Law of Motion from Kepler, developed
1666, published 1687 in Philosophiae Naturalis Principa
Mathematica. The idea of an infinitesimal mathematics came from
Newton in 1663; three years later he had developed his differential
mathematics. His Optics, 1704, put forth the division of light in
color as well as emission theory.
Later Newton lost all interest
in physics, mathematics, and also in the destiny and consequences of his
works. He turned towards chemical and alchemical experiments and studies
of their old traditions. In his old age he was interested in
religious-speculative studies. Before his death he compared his life
with a day, in which a child is playing with sand and mussels and is not
aware anymore of the cosmos at his back. Literature: J.W.N. Sullivan,
Isaac Newton 1642–1727 (London 1938).
◬
In Newton's second edition of his Philosophiae
Naturalis Principa Mathematica of 1713 the definition is "But
I do not define, because it is well known to all of
us."
◬
George Berkeley: Desert
Castle, Thomastown, Ireland 1685–1753 Oxford. English philosopher
and Anglican missionary, Bishop from 1734. Main works: Treatise
Concerning the Principle of Human Knowledge, 1710; Alciphron,
about ethics and free thinkers, 1732; Siris, concerning
metaphysical questions. See: Riddles of Philosophy.
Berkeley said: "One has to do it in such a way": e.g., as in
Paragraph 113 of Principles of Human Knowledge. In the writing
De Motu (From Motion) is written in Paragraph 43:
"Motion, even though perceived clearly by the senses, was
darkened, but not because of its own being, but far more through
commentaries by learned philosophers."
◬
In the work Optice by Newton, which is the
Latin translation of his Optics (1704), published by Samuel
Clarke in 1706 and approved with additions made by Newton, the formula
appears only at the end of the book at the so-called 28th Problem:
"If these questions are answered in the right way, could we then
not ascertain the phenomenon that there is a being, unbodily,
intelligent, which can perceive the endless universe as it were with its
sense organs, and which seems to look into the innermost and is
surrounding it with its all-embracing presence, while that in us that is
usually feeling and thinking are only handed-down pictures in which we
then perceive and observe our organs?" This thought seems not only
to be Newton's, but was also presented in a similar way by Henry More,
the Platonist from Cambridge who was a friend of Newton.
◬
For his polemic concerning
Newton's color theory, see Rudolf Steiner, Goethe the Scientist
(New York: Anthroposophic Press, 1950), especially the Introduction,
"Goethe, Newton and the Physicists"; see also the
forthcoming book, Heinrich O. Proskauer, The Rediscovery of Color
(Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic Press).
◬
Leibnitz: Leipzig
1646–1716 Hanover. Philologist, mathematician, physicist, lawyer,
statesman, priest. Mostly living at princely courts, traveling a lot.
Discoverer of the Infinitesimal Calculus 1686, independently of
Newton.
◬
In his writing The
Analyst (The Analyst, 1734, included in the book Writings
about the Origin of Mathematics and Physics) the Table of Contents
is in the form of 50 theses. No. 7, for example, is as follows:
"Objections against the Secrets of Belief Which are Made Unfairly
by Those who Admit Them in Science;" or No. 13: "The Rule
for the Flux of Potency is Achieved through Unfair Reasoning;" and
No. 22: "With the Help of a Double Mistake Analysts Come to their
Truth, but not to Science, in which They do not even Know How They Came
to Their Own Conclusions." From the Polemic Dispute, which
follows The Analyst, an example is: "No big name on this
earth will ever cause me to take unclear things for clear ones. They
think of one as if it were a crime to think one could see further than
Sir Isaac Newton, even above him. I am convinced though that they speak
for the feelings of many others. But there are also some ... who think
and feel it unfair to copy some great man's shortcomings, and who see no
crime in wanting to see further than Sir Isaac Newton, but further than
the whole of mankind."
◬
Prepared by Mach and Lorentz, developed by
Einstein, Special Theory of Relativity 1905, Common Theory of
Relativity 1916. Made it necessary to revise Newton's Mechanics with
the help of non-Euclidean Geometry. See also Riddles of
Philosophy and Georg Unger, Von Bidden, Physicalischer
Begriffe, Part 3 (Stuttgart: 1967), pages
100–122.
◬
Lessing, Gottfried Ephraim: Kamenz/Lausitz
1729–1781 Brunswick. Dramatist, essayist, critic. Opens a new
epoch in German literature and an. His last writing, "The
Education of the Human Race," (1780) finds it necessary to
postulate reincarnation for the sake of the development of the human
race. See Riddles of Philosophy.
◬
The reason was a
controversy in the magazine Die Drei of 1921–1922, pages
1107 and 1114, as well as in the following years publication (see pages
172–330 about the reality of atoms). See Rudolf Steiner's First
Scientific Lecture Course: Light Course (Forest Row, England:
Steiner Schools Fellowship, 1977).
◬
John Locke: Wrington
by Bristol 1632–1704 Oates, Essex. Theologian, philosopher, and
physician. Because raised Protestant and Puritan, he was persecuted in
England and had to flee to Holland until after the English Revolution of
1689. From 1675–1689 Locke worked with many interruptions at his
main work. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, 1690.
Originally he had planned a critical presentation of the already
recognized teaching of primary and secondary sense characteristics, but
then it grew to a perception theory or world view. His Essay was
published 4 times in his lifetime. See Riddles of Philosophy,
The Philosophy of Freedom, trans. Michael Wilson (Spring Valley,
NY: Anthroposophic Press, 1964) and "Cardinal Nicolas of
Cusa" in Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern
Age.
◬
Richard Wahle:
1857–1935, Vienna, Professor of Philosophy. Only valued
perceptions, imaginations, and feelings, but rejected all philosophy
hitherto written as theories of cognition. The "Ego" is for
him "a summary of surface-like, physiologically accompanied pieces
of consciousness, which are brought into being by invisible
forces." Some writings: The Whole of Philosophy and Its
End, 1894; About the Mechanism of the Spiritual Life, 1906;
The Tragic Comedy of Wisdom, 1915; Development of
Characters, 1928; Basics of a New Psychiatry,
1931.
◬
See Rudolf
Steiner, The Philosophy of Freedom, Chapter 4.
◬
Immanuel Kant:
1724–1804. Lived in Koenigsberg, which he seldom left.
Philosopher, scientist, mathematician. Professor in Koenigsberg
1770–1794. Critique of Pure Reason, 1781. Its popular
edition Dissertation on Any Future Metaphysics, 1783, his ethic
Critique of Practical Reason, 1788, aesthetic and natural
theology is handled in Critique of Judgment, 1790. He wrote the
first mechanical cosmology 1755. It was taken up and changed by Laplace
(1796) and known as the Kant-LaPlace Theory. Rudolf Steiner's exposition
on Kant's theory is found in Truth and Knowledge, The
Philosophy of Freedom, and An Autobiography, ed. Paul M.
Alien, 2nd ed. (Blauvelt, NY: Steinerbooks, Garber Communications,
1980).
E.g. in Critique of Pure Reason,
"Transcendental Aesthetic, Common Remarks": "We wanted
to say that all our opinions are nothing but the conception of the
appearance; that the things we look at are not actually what we take
them for, nor is their relation constituted as they appear to us, and
that if we would suspend our subject or even our subjective constitution
of our senses as a whole, the whole constitution, all relationships of
objects in space and time, even time and space itself would disappear.
They would only exist in us, not as phenomena in
themselves."
◬
August Weismann, Frankfurt A.M. 1834–1914
Freiburg. Biologist, genetic scientist. Theory of polarity between cells
(soma) and seed plasma. Determinants as heredity carriers. Writing:
Studies on the Descent Theory.
◬
Goethe's recital from
Faust I, Act 1, Scene 2, "Night," Gothic Room, Wagner
and Faust:
"My friend, the time of past Is a book with
seven seals. What you call the Spirit of Time Is fundamentally
the Gentleman's own spirit, In which the times reflect
themselves."
◬
Henry
Poincaré: Nancy 1854–1912 Paris. Author of the popular
philosophical writings Science and Hypothesis (1902), The
Value of Science (1905), Science and Method (1909), and
Last Thoughts (1912). The lecture in question was held by
Poincaré shortly before his death in a lecture cycle
Conferences de Foi et de Vie printed in Le Materialisme
Actuel with M.M. Bergson, H. Poincaré, Ch. Gide, Ch. Wagner,
Firm Roz, De Witt-Guizotfriedel, Gaston Rion. (Paris: 1918), page
53.
◬
Mathias Jakob Schleiden:
Hamburg 1804–1881 Frankfurt A.M. Lawyer, physician, and, mainly,
biologist. Developed a cell formation theory in Contributions to
Phylogenesis (1838).
◬
Theodor Schwann: Neuss
1810–1882 Cologne, biologist. Founded the cell theory with his
Microscopic Examinations of the Harmony in Structure and Growth of
Animals and Plants (1839).
◬
In the night from New Year's Eve to New Year's Day
1922/23 the Goetheanum burned down. It was built in ten years, with the
help of various artists from many countries. This primarily wooden
building, in which each surface and corner was formed artistically (see
Steiner, Ways to a New Style in Architecture [London:
Anthroposophical Publishing Co. and New York: Anthroposophic Press,
1927]) had been designed in all details by Rudolf Steiner who also
managed the construction work through all these years. From the first of
January on, the activities had to be transferred into the so-called
"Schreinerei," a building that was used during the
construction of the Goetheanum. For the work itself, Rudolf Steiner did
not allow any interruption; the afternoon after the fire, the
"Three Kings Play" was performed, as was written on the
invitations of the ongoing course (see Christmas Plays from
Obervfer, trans. A.C. Harwood [London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1973]).
Rudolf Steiner introduced it with a short address, in which he spoke the
following words: "great suffering knows how to keep silent about
what it is feeling ... The building that was created in ten years
through the love and compassion of innumerable friends of the movement
was destroyed in one night. But just today the silent suffering
experiences what our friends have put in this work. Since we feel that
everything we do in our movement is necessary in our present
civilization, we will want to continue whatever we can in the given
frame, and therefore even in this hour as the flames outside still burn
and rise, although such suffering is present, still perform this play
which we promised our participants in connection with our course, and
which these participants expect. I also will hold the lecture I offered,
here in the 'Schreinerei' this evening at 8:00 P.M."
(printed in Ansprachen zu den Weihnachtsspielen aus Altem
Volkstum [Dornach: Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1974], GA Bibl. Nr. 274).
The beginning of the course's lecture was then devoted to the fire,
which is printed in The Younger Generation (Spring Valley, NY:
Anthroposophic Press, 1984).
◬
One can find the basic
reality explained in the chapter "Sleep and Death" in An
Outline Of Occult Science and in Knowledge of the Higher Worlds
and Its Attainment (Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic Press,
1983).
◬
Paracelsus,
Theophrastus von Hohenheim: Einsiedein, Kanton Schwytz 1493–1541
Salzburg, Md. Ferrara, Professor in Basel. Accomplished physician,
scientist, and philosopher. Wrote about chemistry, medical science,
biology, astronomy, astrology, alchemy, and theology. The myths about
Paracelsus as goldmaker, magician, or charlatan were made up after his
death and distorted the picture of his character. Most complete work
published by Karl Sudhoff (fourteen volumes). See Riddles of
Philosophy.
◬
Helmont, Johann Baptist
van: Brussels 1577–1644. Physician and iatrochemist. He managed
the differentiation and separation of gases (hydrogen, carbon). He
coined the name "gas" for the airy state.
◬
See Steiner, Goethe the
Scientist. Especially see Chapters 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12,
15.
◬
Lecture of April 8, 1911, at the 9th International
Philosophical Congress, "The Psychological Foundations of
Anthroposophy," in Rudolf Steiner, Esoteric Development,
Spring Valley, NY: 1982, pp. 25–55.
◬
Rudolf Steiner,
Theosophy (Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic Press, 1971), pp.
1–39.
◬
Rudolf Steiner, Man and the World of Stars: The
Spiritual Communion of Mankind (New York: Anthroposophic Press,
1963), pp. 141–172.
◬
Galileo Galilei: Pisa
1564–1642 Arcetri by Florence. Discovered isochromism in pendulum,
hydrostatic scales, laws of free fall, law of inertia. Numerous
astronomical inventions with self-constructed telescope. An Inquisition
trial resulted in a banning of the Copernican world system. See
Riddles of Philosophy, The Spiritual Guidance of Man, and
Laurenz Muellner's speech, "Die Bedeutung Galilei's fuer die
Philosophie," Vienna 1894. (Reprinted in
Anthroposophie, 1933/34:29).
His Sermons de Motu
Gravium (About the Effects of Gravity) contain the results of
his investigations in Pisa. They first only circulated in manuscript
copies; first edition: 1854. The final version is in the Discorsi e
Dimenstrazioni Mathematiche Intomo a Due Nuove Scieme, published
1638 in Leyden. Also see L. Muellner's speech.
◬
Such
opponents were Bacon, Bruno, Galilei. See Riddles of Philosophy
and the speech of L. Muellner, p. 103.
◬
Johannes
Kepler: Weil der Stadt (Wuerttemberg) 1571–1630 Regensburg.
Mathematician, physicist, astronomer, discoverer of the astronomical
telescope. Astronomer and mathematician to three emperors. Persecuted as
a Protestant. Totally exhausted through his life misery, he died
prematurely at the "Reichstag" at Regensburg, where he hoped
to secure his subsistence. To calculate his three laws of the motion of
the planets he used the observation data of Tycho Brahe, whose follower
he was at the court of Prague. On the other hand, the Copernican
planetary system was the starting point for the finding of the three
laws of the planets. Kepler was the first who tried to interpret the
motion of the planetary orbit and moved the center of force to the sun.
See The Spiritual Guidance of Man and, about the three planetary
laws Das Verhaeltnis der Verschiedenen Naturwissenschaftlichen
Gebiete zur Astronomie (Dornach: Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1981), GA
Bibl. Nr. 323.
◬
Galen:
Pergamon, Asia Minor 129 A.D.–199 Rome. Physician and philosopher.
Studies in Pergamon and travel for study to Corinth, Smyrna, and
Alexandria. Personal physician of Emperor Marcus Aurelius. His one
hundred and fifty medical texts with fifteen commentaries were the basis
for future medicine and pharmacology. One hundred twenty-five texts
concerning philosophy, mathematics, and jurisprudence.
◬
Rudolf Steiner, A
Road to Self Knowledge: The Threshold of the Spiritual World
(London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1975), pp.
19–27,100–106.
◬
This is confirmed in
chemical textbooks. They speak of chemistry as "a primarily
empirical science." In its laws one cannot come to mathematically
definite values but to approximate numbers, whose limits are defined in
tabular form. Therefore authors of chemical subject books need to add
limiting explanations, such as "usually is valid," or
"generally one can say." Chemical laws are mostly derived
from physical laws, as for instance in the main theses of
thermodynamics. It is thought unscientific to think otherwise than
mechanically. Literature: H. Remy, Lehrbuch der Anorganischen
Chemie, 7th ed., 2 vols. (Leipzig: 1954), Volume I, pages
14–23, 37, 50, 71–73.
◬
See Georg Unger, Vom Bilden Physicalischer
Begriffe, Volume 1, pages 41–49 and 57.
◬
Steiner, The Boundaries
of Natural Science, pp. 59–87. Chapters 5 and 6, as well as 7
and 8.
◬
Johannes Scotus
Erigena: also Eriugena, Ireland 810–877 France. Pre-Scholastic
philosopher, theologian with extensive comprehension of language. Came
from Britain to France. Led the Emperor's Academy in Paris
845–877. Finished his translation of Dionysius the Areopagite in
858. His main work was De Divisione Naturae (Division of
Nature), 867. He taught out of a Platonic comprehension. He stood up
for the introduction of the hierarchical order in the worldly
administration of the church. See also Mysticism at the Dawn of the
Modern Age.
◬
The copy
in Greek originated in the fifteenth century. Dionysius was a member of
the Areopag in Athens and a student of the Apostle Paul (Acts 17:34).
The setting up of the 3 times 3 hierarchies by Dionysius was adapted as
dogma by the Catholic church. His writings in Latin translation were
taken up enthusiastically, and were still taken as authentic in the
seventeenth century. See Riddles of Philosophy, The Redemption
of Thinking, Die Ursprungsimpulse der Geisteswissenschaft
(Dornach: Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1974), GA Bibl. Nr. 96, and Otto
Willmann, Geschichte des Idealismus, Volume II, paragraph
59.
◬
See also the personalities
spoken of in Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern
Age.
◬
Jacob Boehme:
Altseidenberg, Goerlitz 1575–1624 Goerlitz. Mystic. His profession
was shoemaker. First writing Aurora, 1612. Further writings from
1619 onwards, despite the prohibition. See Riddles of
Philosophy.
◬
Iatrochemistry: Name from the Greek
"Iatro," physician. Work with homeopathic remedies in
continuation of Paracelsus' (1493–1541) method of healing, in the
beginning with retention of his opinion about sulfur, mercury, and salt.
The Iatrochemical School was established during Paracelsus' last years
of life. It degenerated in the middle of the seventeenth century. In its
place stepped Robert Boyle's chemistry (1627–1691), for which
iatrochemistry had done good preparation. J.B. van Helmont
(1577–1644) was one of the main contributors to Iatrochemical
literature.
◬
Iatromechanics and
Iatromathematics. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries the
proponents of these teachings were nearly all university professors,
while iatrochemistry was represented by a union of practicing
physicians. But that was true only in the Romantic countries and
England. In Italy the main universities were Padua, Pisa, and Rome.
There the teachings were rejected on philosophic grounds, because they
were based on experience. Germany, where both branches worked hand in
hand, was an exception and in a special position.
◬
Georg Ernst Stahl: Ansbach
1650–1734, Berlin. Physician and chemist, Professor of Medicine.
Exponent of Animism and Vitalism and the hypothesis of the "life
forces" in his major work Theoria Medico Vera,
1707.
◬
Offray de la
Mettrie: Malo 1709–1751 Berlin. Physician and writer. Main work is
L'Homme Machine, published in Leyden 1748.
◬
Baron Dietrich von
Hollenbach: Heidesheim, Rheinpfalz 1723–1789 Paris. His main work
Systeme de la Nature ou des Lois du Monde Physique et du Monde
Moral appeared 1770 under the pseudonym Mira-baud. He only
recognized mobile, material atoms, even in regard to thinking, and he
based morals on self love.
◬
Thomas Hobbes: Malmesbury 1588–1679
Hardwicke. English natural philosopher and humanist. Opera
Philosophica, 1688. All phenomena in nature and humanity, even the
psychological ones, are result of mobility of bodies. The social
processes are traced back to mechanical processes. The leading force in
this process is the egoism of the single human being. The state which is
"crushing everything underfoot," he called
"Leviathan" and said: "The natural social condition is
the war of all against all."
◬
See Drawings, pages 92, 95 and compare with the ones on page 125.
◬
See Rudolf Steiner,
The Karma of Vocation
(Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic Press, 1984).
Literature: Adolf Fink has studied the mechanism of human movement
and the heat produced by muscular work, and published in 1857, 1869,
and 1882 Gesammelte Schriften, (1903–06 in German).
◬
In the beginning of the century Rudolf Steiner pointed to the speech
of the philosopher and Prime Minister A.J. Balfour of August 17,
1904, in front of the British Association, immediately after it was
held; see Rudolf Steiner,
Lucifer Gnosis
(Dornach: Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1969), GA Bibl. No. 34, p. 467.
Often Steiner also mentioned the lecture of Max Planck of 1910:
"Die Stellung der Neueren Physic zur Mechanischen
Weltanshaung" in Max Planck,
Physikalische Abhandlungen und Vorträge
(Brunswick, Germany, 1958), Vol. 3, pp. 30–46.
◬
In 1920 a research institute was founded in Stuttgart for physics
and chemistry, with a biological branch through the joint stock
company "Der Kommende Tag." A few years later it
was transferred to Dornach. The first works from the Institute were
published in Der Kommende Tag: Scientific Research Institute
News. It contains Heft I (1921),
"Milzfunktion und Blaettchen Frage"
von L. Kolisko; Heft II (1923),
"Der Villardsche Versuch"
von Dr. Rer. Nat. R.E. Maier; Heft III (1923):
"Physiologischer und Physicalischer Nachweis Kleinster
Entitaeten" von L. Kolisko. Later works appeared in the volumes
Gaea Sophia, Jahrbuch der Wissenschaftlichen
Sektion der Freien Hochschule fuer Geisteswissenschaft am
Goetheanum, Volume I (1926), etc.
◬
From this scientific discussion of January 5 no known copy exists.